Counter-Currents
  • Private Events
  • T&C
  • About
  • Contact
  • Webzine
  • Books
  • Podcasts
  • Videos
  • Donate
  • Paywall
  • Crypto
  • RSS
    • Main feed
    • Podcast feed
    • Videos feed
    • Comments feed
  • Advertise

LEVEL2

Donate Now Mailing list
  • Webzine
  • Books
  • Podcasts
  • Videos
  • Donate
  • Paywall
  • Crypto
  • RSS
    • Main feed
    • Podcast feed
    • Videos feed
    • Comments feed
  • Advertise
  • Recent posts

    • Israel, Gaza, and the War for Your Mind

      Christian Secor

      1

    • Polish-Style Territorial Defense Could Be the Answer to the Risk of Civil War in France

      Olivier Bault

      1

    • Toward a New Spiritual Revolution

      Morris van de Camp

    • Introducing the Counter-Currents Book Club

      Greg Johnson

      1

    • The Fear of Writing

      Mark Gullick

    • Obi-Wan Kenobi

      Trevor Lynch

      1

    • The Homeland Institute’s Third Poll, Part Two: Is National Divorce a Solution?

      David M. Zsutty

    • Tommy Robinson: Fakta vs. emoce a nejnovější lži

      Huntley Haverstock

    • The Worst Week Yet: November 26-December 2, 2023

      Jim Goad

      10

    • Lamentations for a City

      Morris van de Camp

      6

    • The Homeland Institute’s Third Poll, Part One: American Democracy in Crisis

      David M. Zsutty

      1

    • Mike Johnson and Diff’rent Strokes: When Liberal Narratives Collapse

      Travis LeBlanc

      1

    • Using Politics to Segregate the Sexes

      Jim Goad

    • Imagine Jim Goad Singing “Imagine”

      Greg Johnson

      13

    • The Union Jackal, November 2023

      Mark Gullick

      5

    • Christmas Special: Merry Christmas, Infidels!

      Greg Johnson

      30

    • Jonathan Bowden’s The Cultured Thug

      Margot Metroland

      1

    • Le Manifeste Nationaliste Blanc: Introduction à un livre interdit

      Greg Johnson

    • Little Free Library Book Giveaway!

      Cyan Quinn

      5

    • Using Politics to Segregate the Sexes

      Jim Goad

      35

    • The Boondock Saints and Overnight: Troy Duffy’s Career as Cautionary Tale

      Travis LeBlanc

      6

    • David Zsutty Introduces the Homeland Institute: Transcript

      David M. Zsutty

    • It’s White Wednesday! Shop Our Sale Now

      Cyan Quinn

    • Ahsoka

      Trevor Lynch

      5

    • The US Military Excuses an Anti-White Massacre: Black Soldiers & the Houston Riot of 1917

      Dave Chambers

      2

    • “A Few More Steps and We Were . . . On Some Edge of Things”: Staircases That Lead Nowhere, Part 2

      Kathryn S.

      4

    • Counter-Currents Radio Podcast No. 561: An All-Star Thanksgiving Weekend Special

      Counter-Currents Radio

    • Giving Tuesday at Counter-Currents: Help Us Meet Our Match!

      Cyan Quinn

      5

    • “A Few More Steps and We Were . . . On Some Edge of Things”: Staircases That Lead Nowhere, Part 1

      Kathryn S.

      5

    • The Blacks Next Door

      Gunnar Alfredsson

      7

    • Where the Dissident Right Triumphs

      Lipton Matthews

      2

    • Used to Be a Bad Guy: Carlito’s Way at 30

      Mark Gullick

      3

    • The Worst Week Yet: November 19-25, 2023

      Jim Goad

      21

    • Ridley Scott’s Napoleon

      Trevor Lynch

      28

    • Are We (Finally) Living in the World of Atlas Shrugged? Part 2

      Jef Costello

      4

    • The Suppression of the Maryland Moderates During the Civil War

      Morris van de Camp

      2

    • The Anti-Black Plague “Black Death” of 1347-1351 Kills Half of Europe . . . Black Women Most Affected

      Jim Goad

      4

    • We Have Much to be Thankful For

      Greg Johnson

    • All-Star Thanksgiving Weekend Special!

      Greg Johnson

      2

    • Black Friday Special: It’s Time to STOP Shopping for Christmas

      Greg Johnson

      5

    • Are We (Finally) Living in the World of Atlas Shrugged? Part 1

      Jef Costello

      12

    • We Get the Crime We Deserve

      Spencer J. Quinn

      8

    • Nueva Derecha vs. Vieja Derecha, Capítulo 12: La Cuestión Cristiana en el Nacionalismo Blanco

      Greg Johnson

    • Happy Thanksgiving!

      Greg Johnson

      1

    • The Anti-Black Plague: “Black Death” of 1347-1351 Kills Half of Europe . . . Black Women Most Affected

      Jim Goad

      24

    • A Veteran’s Thanksgiving Message

      David M. Zsutty

      3

    • Horses and Heavy Hors d’Oeuvres

      James J. O'Meara

    • Let Elon Cook

      Travis LeBlanc

      3

    • Should We Defend Anti-Semitic Literature?

      Jason Kessler

      8

    • G. Gordon Liddy’s When I Was a Kid, This Was a Free Country, Part 2

      Beau Albrecht

  • Classics Corner

    • A Heroic Vision for Our Time: The Life and Ideas of Colin Wilson

      John Morgan

      12

    • Remembering J. Philippe Rushton (December 3, 1943–October 2, 2012)

      Greg Johnson

      7

    • Herman Husband, Eighteenth Century White Nationalist Pioneer

      Spencer J. Quinn

      10

    • Remembering Henry Williamson (December 1, 1895-August 13, 1977)

      Greg Johnson

    • Black Friday Special: It’s Time to STOP Shopping for Christmas

      Greg Johnson

      5

    • The Holy Mountain, Part 1

      Derek Hawthorne

      1

    • The Holy Mountain, Part 2

      Derek Hawthorne

      2

    • Remembering Krzysztof Penderecki (November 23, 1933-March 29, 2020)

      Alex Graham

    • Thanksgiving Day as a Harvest Festival

      Andrew Hamilton

    • Thanksgiving: The Only Holiday Unique to the American Ethny

      C. F. Robinson

      9

    • The Importance of Believing: Terry Pratchett’s Hogfather

      Howe Abbott-Hiss

      6

    • Remembering Madison Grant (November 19, 1865-May 30, 1937)

      Greg Johnson

      3

    • Remembering Wyndham Lewis (November 18, 1882-March 7, 1957)

      Greg Johnson

    • Remembering Sir Oswald Mosley (November 16, 1896-December 3, 1980)

      Greg Johnson

      4

    • Revolution of the Nation

      Sir Oswald Mosley

    • The Feminine Sexual Counter-Revolution and Its Limitations, Part 1

      F. Roger Devlin

      2

    • The Feminine Sexual Counter-Revolution and Its Limitations, Part 2

      F. Roger Devlin

      41

    • America and Israel: United in Struggle

      Alexander Jacob

      16

    • Zionism vs. White Nationalism

      Spencer J. Quinn

      7

    • Debate on Christianity

      Jonas De Geer and Greg Johnson

      42

    • In Defense of Populism

      Greg Johnson

      6

    • The Politics of Nuclear War, Part 3: Israel and the Bomb

      John Morgan

      30

    • For Leo Yankevich: October 30, 1961 to December 11, 2018

      Juleigh Howard-Hobson

      3

    • The Heresy of Christian Zionism: Israel, Christianity, & Genesis 12.2-3

      Irmin Vinson

      31

    • Philosemitism & Brutality

      Andrew Hamilton

      57

    • Charles Ives, American Composer

      Alex Graham

      8

    • Remembering Friedrich Nietzsche
      (October 15, 1844–August 25, 1900)

      Greg Johnson

      5

    • Remembering Aleister Crowley (October 12, 1875–December 1, 1947)

      Greg Johnson

      10

    • Remembering Ralph Vaughan Williams (October 12, 1872–August 26, 1958)

      Alex Graham

      3

    • Archeofuturist Fiction: Frank Herbert’s Dune

      Greg Johnson

      23

  • Paroled from the Paywall

    • Never the Twain: Notes on Logic and Morality

      Mark Gullick

      18

    • Counter-Currents Radio Podcast No. 557: New Ask Me Anything with Greg Johnson

      Counter-Currents Radio

      3

    • Heil Honey, I’m Home

      Travis LeBlanc

      2

    • Management and Working Remotely

      Morris van de Camp

      1

    • The Protocols of Zion Today, Part 2

      Beau Albrecht

    • The Protocols of Zion Today, Part 1

      Beau Albrecht

      8

    • The Rise and Fall of Ibram X. Kendi

      Beau Albrecht

      14

    • Remembering the Great White Hopes of Boxing

      Travis LeBlanc

      10

    • Race and IQ Differences: An Interview with Arthur Jensen, Part 5

      Arthur Jensen

    • Nueva Derecha vs. Vieja Derecha Capítulo 10: El Peso de Hitler

      Greg Johnson

    • Gerald P. Nye: American Patriot and Midwestern Isolationist, Part 2

      Morris van de Camp

    • Gerald P. Nye: American Patriot and Midwestern Isolationist, Part 1

      Morris van de Camp

    • Looking for Mr. Goodbar: A Tale of Disco-Era Debauchery

      Travis LeBlanc

      26

    • Race & IQ Differences: An Interview with Arthur Jensen, Part 4

      Arthur Jensen

    • For Lesbians Only

      Beau Albrecht

      11

    • Why Cartoons Have Potential: A Response to Travis LeBlanc, Part 2

      White Lion Movement

    • Fictionalizing the Right

      Clarissa Schnabel

      5

    • Jack Hinson’s One-Man War

      Spencer J. Quinn

      2

    • The 12 Black Years Since Jared Taylor’s White Identity

      Mark Gullick

      4

    • Exercise Tips for the Anxious

      Gunnar Alfredsson

      3

    • Race & IQ Differences: An Interview with Arthur Jensen, Part 3

      Arthur Jensen

    • It’s Not All About You

      Spencer J. Quinn

      5

    • Counter-Currents Radio Podcast No. 554 How Often Does Pox Think About the Roman Empire? . . . & Other Matters

      Counter-Currents Radio

    • White Altruism Revealed

      Gunnar Alfredsson

      2

    • The Matter with Concrete, Part 2

      Michael Walker

      2

    • The Matter with Concrete, Part 1

      Michael Walker

      4

    • The Captivity Narrative of Fanny Kelly

      Spencer J. Quinn

      11

    • Race and IQ Differences: An Interview with Arthur Jensen, Part 2

      Arthur Jensen

      3

    • The Unnecessary War

      Morris van de Camp

      3

    • Marx vs. Rousseau

      Stephen Paul Foster

      4

  • Recent comments

    • ArminiusMaximus

      Israel, Gaza, and the War for Your Mind

      Beautifully written. The ending is a perfect summation of the core issue at hand. In the spirit of...

    • Gallus

      Polish-Style Territorial Defense Could Be the Answer to the Risk of Civil War in France

      Great piece of writing contrasting the very real threat that has engulfed towns, cities and could...

    • MC

      Introducing the Counter-Currents Book Club

      Love this

    • nineofclubs

      The Worst Week Yet: November 26-December 2, 2023

      Obregon’s mother may lack certain social graces, but it must be said that her venom - directed at...

    • Kathryn S

      “A Few More Steps and We Were . . . On Some Edge of Things”: Staircases That Lead Nowhere, Part 1

      Wow, what a neat assignment! And that's an interesting observation about the Alpine villagers and...

    • Beau Albrecht

      The Stolen Land Narrative

      That sounds like something that Howard Zinn would come up with, a lying activist pretending to be a...

    • Beau Albrecht

      Obi-Wan Kenobi

      Whew... As Anakin Skywalker once said:  "Noooooooooooooooooooooo!"

    • Alexandra O.

      The Homeland Institute’s Third Poll, Part One: American Democracy in Crisis

      I think that most White people find it easier to get along with others of another political...

    • Will Williams

      Christmas Special: Merry Christmas, Infidels!

      Greg: Kwanzaa is supposed to be a Negro alternative to Christmas. It is a seven-day feast,...

    • Richard Smith

      Imagine Jim Goad Singing “Imagine”

      First time I heard Jim singing "White Room" above, it's damn good!

    • Josephus Cato

      The Worst Week Yet: November 26-December 2, 2023

      I was hoping he would have succeeded in his appeal to SCOTUS.  I'm wondering if it was declined due...

    • DarkPlato

      Lamentations for a City

      I’ll wager Bovarian Motor Works has a large percentage of it by now!

    • Gallus

      Lamentations for a City

      That was a superb article. Thanks for sharing the link to the documentary, I shall watch that with...

    • Fyrdman

      Christmas Special: Merry Christmas, Infidels!

      Interesting article, with interesting reader responses. Here in England, the mercantile Christmas tv...

    • Hamburger Today

      Christmas Special: Merry Christmas, Infidels!

      The 'divine mother and child' is a pre-Christian tableu.Innana, the ‘mother’ figure in the Egyptian...

    • ncleapyear

      Lamentations for a City

      I read somewhere that George Wallace referred to Humphrey as a "pointy head" in the 1968...

    • Kök Böri

      The Worst Week Yet: November 26-December 2, 2023

      Тurscak is either an Ukrainian, or a Pole.

    • DarkPlato

      Lamentations for a City

      Great article. Of course it was all to get whites back for electing Trump. As were the Covid...

    • Fire Walk With Lee

      The Worst Week Yet: November 26-December 2, 2023

      Victims of black on white violence are just experiencing diversity.  Or experiencing cultural...

    • Anne Frank Rizzo

      The Worst Week Yet: November 26-December 2, 2023

      Not only has the Mexican Mafia had white members https://en.m.wikipedia.org/wiki/Joe_%22Pegleg%...

  • Book Authors

    • Beau Albrecht
    • Alain de Benoist
    • Kerry Bolton
    • Jonathan Bowden
    • Collin Cleary
    • Jef Costello
    • Savitri Devi
    • F. Roger Devlin
    • Buttercup Dew
    • Julius Evola
    • Jim Goad
    • Gregory Hood
    • Juleigh Howard-Hobson
    • Greg Johnson
    • Charles Krafft
    • Anthony M. Ludovici
    • Trevor Lynch
    • H. L. Mencken
    • J. A. Nicholl
    • James J. O’Meara
    • Christopher Pankhurst
    • Tito Perdue
    • Michael Polignano
    • Spencer J. Quinn
    • Fenek Solère
    • Irmin Vinson
    • Leo Yankevich
    • Francis Parker Yockey
    • Multiple authors
  • Webzine Authors

    Editor-in-Chief

    • Greg Johnson, Ph.D.

    Featured Writers

    • Beau Albrecht
    • Morris V. de Camp
    • Stephen Paul Foster, Ph.D.
    • Jim Goad
    • Alex Graham
    • Mark Gullick, Ph.D.
    • Greg Johnson, Ph.D.
    • Spencer J. Quinn

    Frequent Writers

    • Aquilonius
    • Anthony Bavaria
    • Alain de Benoist
    • Kerry Bolton, Ph.D.
    • Collin Cleary, Ph.D.
    • Jef Costello
    • F. Roger Devlin, Ph.D.
    • Richard Houck
    • Ondrej Mann
    • Margot Metroland
    • John Morgan
    • Trevor Lynch
    • James J. O’Meara
    • Kathryn S.
    • Thomas Steuben
    • Michael Walker

    Classic Authors

    • Maurice Bardèche
    • Jonathan Bowden
    • Julius Evola
    • Guillaume Faye
    • Ernst Jünger
    • Kevin MacDonald, Ph.D.
    • D. H. Lawrence
    • Charles Lindbergh
    • Jack London
    • H. P. Lovecraft
    • Anthony M. Ludovici
    • Sir Oswald Mosley
    • National Vanguard
    • Friedrich Nietzsche
    • Revilo Oliver
    • William Pierce
    • Ezra Pound
    • Saint-Loup
    • Savitri Devi
    • Carl Schmitt
    • Miguel Serrano
    • Oswald Spengler
    • P. R. Stephensen
    • Jean Thiriart
    • John Tyndall
    • Dominique Venner
    • Leo Yankevich
    • Francis Parker Yockey

    Other Authors

    • Howe Abbott-Hiss
    • Michael Bell
    • Buttercup Dew
    • Giles Corey
    • Bain Dewitt
    • Jack Donovan
    • Richardo Duchesne, Ph.D.
    • Emile Durand
    • Guillaume Durocher
    • Mark Dyal
    • Fullmoon Ancestry
    • Tom Goodroch
    • Andrew Hamilton
    • Robert Hampton
    • Huntley Haverstock
    • Derek Hawthorne
    • Gregory Hood
    • Juleigh Howard-Hobson
    • Alexander Jacob
    • Nicholas Jeelvy
    • Ruuben Kaalep
    • Tobias Langdon
    • Julian Langness
    • Travis LeBlanc
    • Patrick Le Brun
    • G A Malvicini
    • John Michael McCloughlin
    • Millennial Woes
    • Michael O’Meara
    • Christopher Pankhurst
    • Michael Polignano
    • J. J. Przybylski
    • Quintilian
    • Edouard Rix
    • C. B. Robertson
    • C. F. Robinson
    • Herve Ryssen
    • Alan Smithee
    • Fenek Solere
    • Ann Sterzinger
    • Robert Steuckers
    • Tomislav Sunic
    • Donald Thoresen
    • Marian Van Court
    • Irmin Vinson
    • Aylmer Wedgwood
    • Scott Weisswald
  • Departments

    • Book Reviews
    • Movie Reviews
    • TV Reviews
    • Music Reviews
    • Art Criticism
    • Graphic Novels & Comics
    • Video Game Reviews
    • Fiction
    • Poems
    • Interviews
    • Videos
    • English Translations
    • Other Languages
      • Arabic
      • Bulgarian
      • Croatian
      • Czech
      • Danish
      • Dutch
      • Estonian
      • Finnish
      • French
      • German
      • Greek
      • Hungarian
      • Italian
      • Lithuanian
      • Norwegian
      • Polish
      • Portuguese
      • Romanian
      • Russian
      • Slovak
      • Spanish
      • Swedish
      • Ukrainian
    • Commemorations
    • Why We Write
  • Archives
  • Top 100 Commenters
  • Private Events
  • T&C
  • About
  • Contact
Sponsored Links
Spencer J. Quinn CC Giving Tuesday Above Time Coffee Antelope Hill Publishing Paul Waggener IHR-Store American Renaissance Jim Goad The Occidental Observer
Print May 25, 2021 1 comment

Heidegger’s History of Metaphysics, Part Eight:
Kant, Heidegger, & the Critique of Metaphysics

Collin Cleary

Giacomo Balla, Science Against Obscurantism, 1920

6,034 words

Part 1 here, Part 2 here, Part 3 here, Part 4 here, Part 5 here, Part 6 here, Part 7 here

1. Metaphysics, Natural Science, and Nihilism

My last essay ended with the observation that there are clear points of convergence between Kant’s thought and Heidegger’s. This is hardly any accident, of course, since Kant inaugurates the tradition of “transcendental philosophy” that culminates in the phenomenological approach of Husserl and Heidegger. I will have something to say in my next essay about how Heidegger reads Kant in the light of phenomenology. For now, let us focus on one very obvious similarity between the two thinkers: both are forceful critics of the Western metaphysical tradition. It seems reasonable to suppose that Heidegger viewed Kant as a natural ally. Was this the case? How are their critiques of metaphysics similar, and how are they different? I will explore these questions in the present essay. 

The discussion in the previous installment might have led the reader to believe that Kant’s objections to metaphysics are entirely based on epistemological considerations. Kant’s first Critique explores the nature and limits of human reason, and winds up arguing that metaphysics (at least as hitherto practiced) exceeds the bounds of what we can legitimately claim to know. However, Kant was also preoccupied with the moral problems posed by metaphysics. In the preface to the second edition of the first Critique, he attacks the “schools” and “school philosophy,” by which he means rationalism. He states that it is the duty of the schools,

by means of a thorough investigation of the rights of speculative reason, once for all to prevent the scandal which, sooner or later, is sure to break out even among the masses, as the result of the disputes in which metaphysicians (and, as such, finally also the clergy) inevitably become involved to the consequent perversion of their teaching. Criticism alone [i.e., Kant’s “critical philosophy” alone] can sever the root of materialism, fatalism, atheism, free-thinking, fanaticism, and superstition, which can be injurious universally; as well as of idealism and scepticism, which are dangerous chiefly to the schools, and hardly allow of being handed on to the public. [B xxxiv; italics in original] [1]

Here, Kant gives us a list of all the things he has set himself against, emphasizing each target with italics. How does rationalism lead to all of these? In brief, it is by raising men’s hopes, and then dashing them. Rationalist philosophers like Descartes and Leibniz claim they can prove the existence of God and of a moral order to the universe. This seems like a boon to Christians who may harbor fundamental doubts, especially in the face of scientific advance that seems to leave no room at all for God and the moral order. Unfortunately, the arguments of the rationalists are highly problematic, and the result is that there is no agreement among them. Well-meaning individuals seeking to strengthen their faith through the books of these thinkers are bound to be disappointed — and quite possibly delivered into the arms of materialism, fatalism, atheism, free-thinking, fanaticism, and superstition. [2]

Since we discussed Berkeley in the last essay (and the strange coincidence of Berkeley’s ideas and those of Leibniz), it is worth noting that Berkeley held more or less the exact same concern regarding “school philosophy.” In Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous (1713), Hylas says to Philonous,

I was considering the odd fate of those men who have in all ages, through an affectation of being distinguished from the vulgar, or some unaccountable turn of thought, pretended either to believe nothing at all, or to believe the most extravagant things in the world. This however might be borne, if their paradoxes and scepticism did not draw after them some consequences of general disadvantage to mankind. But the mischief lieth here; that when men of less leisure see them who are supposed to have spent their whole time in the pursuits of knowledge professing an entire ignorance of all things, or advancing such notions as are repugnant to plain and commonly received principles, they will be tempted to entertain suspicions concerning the most important truths, which they had hitherto held sacred and unquestionable. [3]

Berkeley believes he can safeguard “the most important truths” by eliminating the concept of matter and arguing that the world just is our ideas. (Readers curious about exactly how this solution is supposed to work are referred to the Dialogues.) For his part, Kant believed that his demolition of metaphysics had saved belief in God and the moral order. Famously, Kant said in the first Critique, “I have therefore found it necessary to deny knowledge, in order to make room for faith” (B xxx; italics in original). However, Kant accomplishes this by simultaneously delimiting both what can be known by metaphysics and by the natural sciences. 

Had Kant simply argued that metaphysics cannot actually make good on its claims concerning God, morality, or anything else, this would not necessarily have put the brakes on materialism, determinism, and atheism. In fact, it could have made them much stronger and more virulent. What was necessary, in addition, was to show that we still had warrant for believing in God and morality, even if there were no reasons for believing in them. Otherwise, one might simply respond to the Kantian critique of metaphysics as follows: “If no one — neither the clergy nor the philosophers — can give good reasons for believing in these ‘sacred’ truths then I shall reject them. Especially since modern science seems to give positive reasons for denying not only any kind of immaterial divinity or soul, but also the reality of human freedom. The universe seems to be thoroughly material, and everything in it appears to be the result of antecedent causes, including human actions.” 

Kant was thoroughly committed to the Enlightenment’s celebration of reason and rejection of religious dogmatism, so why would he not have embraced such a conclusion? The reason is that Kant had an equally strong commitment to the inviolability human dignity — and the basis for human dignity, Kant believed, was the moral consciousness. This means our capacity to freely choose to act according to moral laws — indeed, to freely “legislate” the moral law for ourselves. No other animal is aware of the idea of the good, an idea which is counterfactual; i.e., knowledge of the good tells us not what is, but what ought to be. No other creature (that we know of) feels itself bound by obligations to such an idea. 

The sense in which we are “bound” by the good or the moral is quite different from how we, and other creatures, are bound physical laws such as the law of gravity. When I fall and hit the ground, we say that my body “obeyed” the law of gravity, but the truth is that I could not have disobeyed. I can disobey the moral law, however. I must freely choose to obey moral injunctions and, furthermore, it is not enough, Kant insists, to merely behave in accord with morality; my actions must instead flow from a free commitment to moral principle. For example, I might perform an act of generosity simply because it will curry the favor of others. If I do, then I am being generous; I am outwardly conforming to a moral rule that enjoins generosity. However, since my action is performed from ulterior motives and not out of a pure and simple commitment to the moral principle, my action deserves no moral credit (no praise, in other words). I acted generously, but for the wrong reasons. My action was not immoral, it was actually in accord with morality; but it was non-moral, because the accord was merely outward.

To change the example a bit, suppose that I acted generously because I am in fact somehow determined to always be generous, and that I have no choice in the matter. (Suppose I am a genetic freak, “programmed” to always be generous, or suppose I have received a post-hypnotic suggestion to do so.) Would my generosity be moral, or deserve moral credit? Kant answers that it would not. If I cannot help being generous, if I have no choice in the matter, then I no more deserve moral credit for my generosity than I do for my respiration or the circulation of my blood, which I also have no choice about. It follows from all the above that freedom, or free will, is a necessary condition of morality. If we are not free to choose our actions, and to act according to different intentions, then morality is impossible. This is a problem that Hume had already recognized. 

The trouble is that the modern scientific worldview has no place for freedom. It insists that everything that happens is governed by the principle of sufficient reason: everything is determined by causes or reasons. To put it crudely, everything that happens is made to happen by something else. Science applies to human action the same principle it applies to the behavior of animals and non-living things: it searches for the causes that compel us to act in particular ways. Thus, science will typically attempt to explain all of our actions on the basis of environmental or biological factors (heredity, hormones, etc.). “Freedom,” to the scientist, seems to be a cause that is itself uncaused; it seems to violate the principle of sufficient reason. To be consistent, the scientist must reject it as a fantasy. He will insist that though we might believe that we freely choose to be generous, in fact our actions are determined by antecedent causes. And even in Kant’s time, scientists were able to present some convincing explanations for what “causes” us to do this or that. 

For Kant, this presented an enormous problem. On the one hand, he could not deny, nor did he want to deny, the power of science to explain the world around us, and to explain much about ourselves. Yet science seems to reject freedom, and without freedom there is no morality. Science thus seems to undermine human dignity, turning us into nothing more than a pretentious variety of ape that deludes itself into thinking it is free. For Kant, this conclusion was intolerable — not just because it is offensive, but also because it denies my very real, vivid, and compelling experience of myself as acting freely according to certain intentions. 

You can buy Collin Cleary’sWhat is a Rune? here

2. Man the Unnatural Animal

Kant’s solution to this problem was to delimit the sphere within which science can make claims. [4] In the previous essay in this series, I explained Kant’s distinction between “phenomena” and “things as they are in themselves.” Phenomena are objects as they appear to us, whereas things in themselves are those same objects considered insofar as they do not appear. Right now, I am experiencing the phenomenal laptop — the laptop as it appears to me. As to the laptop as it is in itself, as it exists independently of my knowledge, this, by definition, I can never know. Now, Kant leaves open the possibility that things in themselves might be quite different from how they appear to us. [5] And he leaves open the possibility that there might be all sorts of things that exist independent of our experience that we are simply not equipped to know. Those things also have the status of things in themselves, for Kant, since they can never appear, and we may speak very loosely of their inhabiting the “realm” of things in themselves. [6] 

Now, the relevance of this distinction for the problem of freedom and morality is as follows. Kant argues that science, since it is based in observation and experiment, is restricted to the domain of phenomena. In other words, it is empirical: it makes sense out of the world that appears to us. This is the case even when it discovers objects that do not appear to the naked eye. These still “appear” to the scientist in some manner; for example, under a microscope or as readings on instruments. Further, the scientific approach, for Kant, is simply a conscious, methodical application of the categories and judgment forms of the understanding which he argues, in the first Critique, already operate in an unconscious, pre-reflective manner in structuring empirical knowledge. As to the realm of things as they are in themselves, science can say absolutely nothing about that. 

Kant affirms that though we think of ourselves as free we never actually have a sensory intuition of “freedom,” and the sciences, again, seem to exclude the possibility. In short, we do not appear to ourselves to be free; there is no experience of freedom in the phenomenal realm. [7] But what about in the realm of things as they are in themselves? As I am in myself, independently of how I appear to myself, to my awareness, might I be free? Kant thinks that this is a definite possibility, on the principle that objects as they are in themselves may be quite different from their appearances. However, since we cannot know things in themselves, we cannot prove that this is the case. This need not disturb us, though, since Kant affirms that we can and do think ourselves as “noumenally” free. Further, we are actually compelled to believe this; it is an inescapable feature of our intellectual constitution. (Yes, ironically, we are compelled to believe that we are free.) 

Kant is entirely correct in this latter claim, which can be verified by anyone who simply reflects on the last time he made a moral choice (any sort of choice would do, but let’s focus on moral choices). Consider: when you decided you had an obligation to, for example, tell the truth in a given situation, was it not accompanied by the strong conviction that you were choosing to do this, and could have chosen otherwise? Our minds are built in such a way to believe this — it is part of the a priori “programming” we discussed extensively in the last essay. It is knowledge of ourselves held independently of sense experience, because, as we have seen, the senses unaided give us no intuition of freedom, nor do the senses when augmented and operationalized in the service of science.

This means, in short, that Kant has placed human freedom, our very essence and the basis for what we think of as human dignity, beyond the reach of the empirical sciences. There is absolutely nothing that could be brought forward by the sciences that could shake our conviction that we are free. Now, readers may balk at this. Isn’t my belief in human freedom shaken every time I read a new book on, say, the evidence for genetic determinism? No, it is not. For as soon as I put the book down and find myself in a situation where I am called upon to make a moral choice — say, the choice to tell the truth or to be generous — I will once more be seized by the conviction that my choice is free and could be otherwise. That book will be completely forgotten.

We may also note that Kant “saves” belief in God and a moral order (i.e., cosmic justice) in a similar fashion. Kant argues that the human moral consciousness requires the tacit belief in a kind of “ordering principle” that will eventually bring about justice, even if we do not see justice done here and now. [8] When you see the unjust going unpunished (or the just being punished) you may notice that your thoughts are accompanied by a conviction that seems to say, if it spoke, “Wait. This will not stand. In the end, these wrongs will be righted.” This is another a priori conviction that seems universal to human thought (though it expresses itself differently in different cultural contexts [9]). It is the tacit belief that there is a kind of cosmic justice at work — and this presupposes some kind of cosmic intelligence that sorts things out. 

Kant is not saying that God and a moral order exist; he is saying that we are so constituted as to believe that they exist. And if we did not, then we might quickly give up on trying to be moral, since empirical knowledge teaches us that injustice very frequently goes unpunished. Why strive to be moral when we continually see the good suffering and the wicked getting off scot-free? Our tacit conviction that wrongs will or must be put right, though it is not based on anything empirical, keeps us plugging away, trying to be virtuous and hoping for the best. 

These arguments have been the source of great controversy. However, our focus here is on Kant’s treatment of human freedom, because here we see an interesting coalescence between Kant and Heidegger. Kant safeguards freedom and human dignity from the threat of scientific materialism and “fatalism” by quite literally locating these in the mysterious world of things as they are in themselves. It is important to see that the implication of this is that Kant is in effect declaring that human nature is not a part of nature at all, and cannot ultimately be understood in naturalistic terms.

Interestingly, Heidegger is basically in complete agreement with Kant on this score. The agreement is in terms of the broad outlines of Kant’s position, not in terms of its detail. Heidegger also rejects the idea that there is any way to understand human nature, Dasein, naturalistically. But it is not just the human moral consciousness that Heidegger places beyond the reach of naturalism, but the whole of transcendental subjectivity (which is also a clear implication of Kant’s position). For Heidegger, meaning only exists for human beings, and transcendental subjectivity is the source of all meaning. 

To put the matter as simply as possible: things only show up as “meaningful” for human consciousness. Meanings are only “for us.” We deal with things we take to have meanings at every moment of our lives (I know what each thing in front of me right now is; I know the meaning it has for me, or for us). But except in cases where we have to consciously struggle to discover what something is, my experience of the world is one in which things seem to show up with meanings already “attached.” Or, to put it another way, I am always seeing things through the meanings they already have for me. I am not consciously aware of doing any “work” to bring about this experience of a world saturated with meaning. In fact, this is because the “work” is done by transcendental subjectivity, operating behind the scenes. [10] 

Now, the meanings we encounter in our experience of the world include the sort of meanings ascribed to objects by the natural sciences. The scientist, too, experiences the world as saturated with meaning, though some of the ways in which objects show up as meaningful for him may be quite beyond the capacity of the laymen. Transcendental subjectivity is a necessary condition for scientific meaning as well, because, as noted above, it is a necessary condition for all meaning-giving. All scientific attempts at making things meaningful presuppose transcendental subjectivity as the horizon within which those things become meaningful in a scientific manner. Therefore, since meaning in the empirical sciences presupposes transcendental subjectivity, the sciences cannot account for, cannot explain transcendental subjectivity. Human nature is, in short, beyond the reach of naturalism.

There is an important caveat we must add to the above account, however. Although Heidegger begins from the Kantian-Husserlian understanding of transcendental subjectivity, he later comes to reject the language of “subjectivity” altogether. (This is a function of his critique of the representationalist tradition, which leads him to reject the traditional subject-object dichotomy.) Thus, transcendental subjectivity comes to be recast as “the Clearing” (Lichtung). I have discussed this concept at length in the first essay that launched this series, “Heidegger Against the Traditionalists.” 

In moving beyond the language of subjectivity, Heidegger believes he is being truer to our experience when we try to give a phenomenological description of how what has been called “transcendental subjectivity” shows up for us. The “transcendental structures” discussed by Kant and the tradition he inaugurated do not in fact show up for us as “subjective”; there is nothing “selflike” or personal about them. [11] Instead, they seem to be an other within which objects become meaningful and to which we seem to be mysteriously attuned; an other that is not in any way empirical (i.e., not known to the senses), but also inescapably real, since all things are knowable or meaningful only within the “light” given by these transcendental structures. Now, if we identify transcendental subjectivity with human nature, as I did earlier, then Heidegger’s shift to the language of the Clearing has an important implication: human nature is revealed not only as nothing natural, it is also, in an important sense, nothing human. We do not possess the Clearing; in a real sense, it possesses us. But what we are is defined in relation to it. 

You can buy Collin Cleary’s Summoning the Gods here.

3. The Roots of Metaphysics and Science

It is now time to step back and assess where we have arrived in our understanding of the Kant-Heidegger relationship. To sum up: I began this entire discussion by noting that while Kant’s criticisms of metaphysics are epistemological in nature, what motivates those criticisms is his awareness of the moral problems posed by metaphysics. It leads, he thinks, to skepticism, atheism, materialism, etc. — all of which may be summed together, conveniently, in one concept: nihilism. However, merely to demonstrate the impossibility of rationalist metaphysics would not be enough, since this would likely deliver well-meaning people into the arms of the scientific materialists — and thus, once more, into nihilism. Kant’s answer to this is to delineate the nature and limits of human knowledge in such a way that metaphysics is defeated and, simultaneously, the sphere in which science can make its claims is strictly limited. The result is that Kant makes a space, as it were, in which human nature can exist unmolested by empiricism and skepticism — and with it freedom and moral conviction, which are the source of human dignity and alone give meaning to life. 

Needless to say, Heidegger is also worried about nihilism. With Kant, he believes that the Western metaphysical tradition leads to it. And, like Kant, he also sees modern science as an expression of nihilism, in its attempts not just to manipulate and control all of nature, but to reduce the human to a natural object. Further, both philosophers see metaphysics and modern science as having a common root, though they give very different accounts of what this is. 

For Kant, the common root is the “ideas of reason.” These have the status of “regulative ideals”: ideals that motivate us to keep thinking, investigating, and synthesizing our knowledge. In his Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, Kant lists three such ideals: we seek knowledge of the “complete subject,” knowledge of the complete “series of conditions,” and knowledge of the “complete complex of that which is possible.” Kant refers to these ideals respectively as “psychological,” “cosmological,” and “theological.” These are part of the a priori constitution of the mind and they serve to motivate, among other things, the scientific quest. Scientists seek complete knowledge of the self, of the causal chain that is the universe, and of the ultimate laws and conditions that determine what may or may not exist in this universe. Science will never actually attain such complete knowledge, but in striving for this goal science continues to advance. 

Now, metaphysics happens, according to Kant, when the ideas of reason get hypostatized; i.e., when they go from being regulative ideals to being misconstrued as actually existing “things.” For example, the psychological idea postulates a “complete subject” about which we strive to attain complete knowledge, but does not assert the actual existence of any such thing. However, the metaphysician imagines that the complete subject is indeed an actually existing thing that exists right now, whole and entire, beyond the sensory realm; a “substance.” He dubs it “the soul.” The cosmological idea is similarly hypostatized as “the cosmos” considered as a totality existing in its own right. [12] The theological idea, needless to say, is hypostatized as God. 

Thus, for Kant metaphysics has the status of a perversion of reason. It is a kind of sickness that human beings often fall into, given the tendencies of the human mind. Metaphysics is not a legitimate endeavor in its own right; it is merely a deluded pretender to the mantel of science. By contrast, the empirical sciences, motivated by the regulative ideals of reason in their positive function, produce real knowledge and are benign — so long as they know their place. 

Heidegger entirely rejects this understanding of metaphysics, and of the relation of metaphysics to science. To avoid equivocation, we must note first of all that “metaphysics” has a broader connotation for Heidegger than it does for Kant. Indeed, what he refers to as “the metaphysical tradition” means more than just the writings of certain philosophers. Heidegger believes, in fact, that philosophers primarily give voice to the spirit of the times. “Metaphysics” thus refers to broader cultural trends. Now, arguably Heidegger does see metaphysics as a perversion — as a falling away from a more authentic relationship to Being, and as culminating in nihilism. However, he does not make the sort of distinction that Kant does between metaphysics and science. In fact, it is actually possible to say that for Heidegger modern science can be located within the “metaphysical tradition.” Just how is this the case?

First, Heidegger famously claims that the metaphysical tradition “forgets Being,” by which he really means that it forgets the Clearing. Recall that the Clearing (aka transcendental subjectivity) is the fundamental condition for meaning. It is only within the space opened up by the Clearing that beings become meaningful for us. (Again, for a fuller discussion of this point, see my essay “Heidegger Against the Traditionalists.”) The metaphysical tradition “forgets” the Clearing in which beings are, and discourses entirely about beings, taking them as ultimate. This claim is original with Heidegger (indeed it is the Heideggerean claim), but it has an analogue in Kant’s critical philosophy. Kant, remember, rejects the idea that transcendental subjectivity/human nature can be understood naturalistically, i.e., in terms of natural objects or forces or conditions (again, because “nature” is only given within transcendental subjectivity, not the other way around). In Heideggerean language, this error consists in confusing Being (or the Clearing) with beings, or trying to understand the ontological (what relates to Being) in terms of the ontic (what relates to beings).

Furthermore, the metaphysical tradition understands beings in terms of their availability to human subjects for understanding and manipulation. What counts as a “being” is what is available to human consciousness. This process begins in Plato, for whom a being is a form or eidos, which literally means “the look” of something, presented to human awareness. (See my essay on Platonism.) In its modern inflection, metaphysics issues in “representationalism”: beings are understood as what is “thrown against” a human subject, or what stands opposed to us, ready to be “represented” within the subject’s interiority, and ready to be mastered and controlled. How? Through the scientific method, of course.

For Heidegger, it is representationalism, in fact, that constitutes the common root of both modern metaphysics and modern science. Thus, the most fundamental response to both consists in a critique of representationalism. We can also make an even stronger claim: nihilism is made possible by representationalism, since representationalism constitutes the foundation both of modern metaphysics and of the ambitions of modern science. Thus, a response to nihilism must include, at the very least, a critique of representationalism. It must also include, of course, an alternative to representationalism — and we will be exploring Heidegger’s alternative in future essays. 

Now, it is fascinating to note that good old Berkeley, despite all his faults, saw representationalism as the villain of modern history as well. Berkeley, as I noted in my last essay, affirms a version of phenomenalism: he argues that all that exists are ideas in minds. He rejects representationalism because it holds that ideas are ideas of something; but Berkeley, again, rejects anything existing outside the mind’s ideas. Further, he believes that representationalism leads to what we would call nihilism. In his Philosophical Commentaries, Berkeley states “the supposition that things are distinct from ideas takes away all real truth and consequently brings in a universal scepticism, since all our knowledge and contemplation is confined barely to our own ideas.” [13] In other words, our ideas are the only objects of which we are directly aware. But if we hold to the representationalist model and postulate that those ideas are somehow “copies” of things existing independently of them, we will forever be ensnared by scepticism, since there is no knowledge of those independent things, and thus no way to tell if our ideas faithfully copy them or not. 

Berkeley’s solution: reject representationalism and affirm that the ideas we know directly are the only objects that exist (our ideas do not copy the world, they are the world). The problem is that Berkeley in effect rejects only half of representationalism: the contention that ideas correspond to things outside our minds. However, he retains the representationalist claim that we are directly aware of (internal) ideas. As Kant might have put it, he takes “ideas” as things in themselves which are immediately, transparently, and thus miraculously given to us. But this is, in fact, the most problematic aspect of representationalism. To repeat something of an oversimplification I offered in my last essay: Berkeley eliminates the “out there” of representationalism while preserving the “in here.”

Given the centrality of representationalism to Heidegger’s critique of metaphysics, we must inquire about how Kant situates himself with respect to it. The short answer is that he also sets himself against representationalism. But how successful is his response? Our answer to this question will really determine how we will have to situate Kant in Heidegger’s account of the history of ideas: does Kant really succeed in overcoming metaphysics, or does he buy into some of its root assumptions? And what of Kant’s account of Being? I have thus far said nothing about this. We will explore these issues in the next installment.

*  *  *

Counter-Currents has extended special privileges to those who donate $120 or more per year.

  • First, donor comments will appear immediately instead of waiting in a moderation queue. (People who abuse this privilege will lose it.)
  • Second, donors will have immediate access to all Counter-Currents posts. Non-donors will find that one post a day, five posts a week will be behind a “paywall” and will be available to the general public after 30 days.

To get full access to all content behind the paywall, sign up here:

Notes

[1] I am using Norman Kemp Smith’s translation of The Critique of Pure Reason (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1965). Reference is to the marginal pagination, standard in all editions of the Critique. “A” refers to the pagination of the first edition (1781), “B” to the second edition (1787).

[2] Possibly the two less obvious points here concern “fanaticism [Schwärmerei] and superstition [Aberglauben].” Here Kant refers to a perversion of religious belief — what Hume called “superstition and enthusiasm.” For example, the adoption of peculiar religious cults, such as fundamentalism (a belief in the literal truth of the Bible). This can result from an encounter with rationalism because rationalism tends to breed “misology”: an antipathy to reason, leading to an attraction to its opposite. By “fatalism” (Fatalismus), Kant means determinism, which denies human freedom. What of “idealism and scepticism”? Note that Kant says these are “dangerous chiefly to the schools.” By “idealism” he means the position that nothing exists save “ideas.” By “scepticism” he means a position like Hume’s, which held that if something exists beyond our ideas, we cannot know it. These afflictions are a danger to intellectuals or academics, but it is obvious that there is little danger that they will be adopted by the public, in the way that materialism or atheism might become widely influential. 

[3] George Berkeley, Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous, ed. Robert Merrihew Adams (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing, 1979), 7-8.

[4] To be clear, Kant does not claim to legislate such a limit; he claims to have discovered it. 

[5] Indeed, things in themselves must be quite different from how they appear to us, since, for one thing, they are not in space and time. For an explanation of this, see my previous essay on Kant.

[6] Although speaking of a “realm” or “world” of things in themselves is almost unavoidable, it should not be taken literally. The reason is that it seems to entail the “in here”/“out there” distinction (the “world” in here, in my mind, and the “world” out there) that is at the root of the representationalist paradigm that Kant is, in fact, trying to overcome. Kant’s relationship to representationalism is problematic, and I will explore it in the next essay.

[7] At the end of the previous section I noted that we have a vivid and compelling “experience” of ourselves as free. Yet just now I have claimed that for Kant we do not “appear” to ourselves as free. Isn’t this a contradiction? No, because “appearance” is always used in Kantian philosophy to mean sensory appearance. I do experience myself as free, but not in the sense that I see, hear, touch, taste, or smell freedom. So what sort of “experience” of freedom is there? This is a question Kant cannot really answer, because he does not have a developed concept of the sort of experience that we are having when we become aware of aspects of subjectivity that are not given by the senses. What his philosophy is missing, in fact, is the idea of phenomenology — a type of second-order “experience” with its own unique, non-sensory form of awareness and its own unique forms of evidence. 

[8] This position has roots in Leibniz’s philosophy, as I argued here.

[9] For example, one culture may postulate that the wicked are punished in the afterlife, while the good go to a place of reward. Another culture may postulate reincarnation, in which one gets one’s just desserts through being reborn in either a more desirable situation, or a less desirable one.

[10] For more information, see my essay “Heidegger Against the Traditionalists.”

[11] This move on Heidegger’s part is analogous to the response of Schelling and Hegel to Kantianism, as it was re-invented by J.G. Fichte (to whom I will devote a later essay). Fichte had recast Kantian transcendental subjectivity (or, in language truer to Kant, “the transcendental unity of apperception”) as the “Absolute Ego.” But, as Schelling was the first to ask, why treat this as an “ego” (as an “I”) when there is nothing personal, self-like, or egoic about it? The result was the shift to the language of “the Absolute,” which transcends the subject-object distinction entirely. There are very interesting parallels to Heidegger’s thought in these ideas, and I believe that his indebtedness to the “Absolute Idealists” has not been sufficiently appreciated. But there are also important differences. 

[12] Of the three acts of hypostatization, the cosmological one is the most difficult to understand. Kant is not saying that the cosmos does not exist, in the sense of saying that these here things don’t exist. What he means is that “the cosmos” is an idea of the total unity of these here things. It is an idea of a “one,” and science does indeed operate with the ideal of working toward knowledge of how all things are part of one unified system. Nevertheless, this is merely an ideal. If we claim that there is a unified system existing right now, a cosmos, then we have hypostatized the ideal. This shows up when metaphysicians raise such questions as “what is the cause of the universe?” This question assumes a cosmos that is “thinglike”; it assumes that the cosmos is a kind of individual (a one) that something else (another individual) could “cause.”

[13] Quoted in Frederick Copleston, A History of Philosophy, Vol. V: Hobbes to Hume (New York: Image Books, 1985), 228.

 

Enjoyed this article?

Be the first to leave a tip in the jar!

Instant Echeck GreenPay™
$

Related

  • David Zsutty Introduces the Homeland Institute: Transcript

  • Must Jews Be Able to Feel Safe in Germany?

  • Never the Twain: Notes on Logic and Morality

  • Follow-Up to the Homeland Institute’s Second Poll

  • Judgment Day for Israel and Palestine

  • Some Thoughts about Virtue Regimes

  • Politics vs. Self-Help

  • Remembering Martin Heidegger: September 26, 1889–May 26, 1976

Tags

beingCollin ClearyDaseindie LichtungEdmund Husserlepistemologyfree willfreedomGodHeidegger's History of MetaphysicsImmanuel KantjusticeknowledgeMartin Heideggermaterialismmeaningmetaphysicsmoralitynihilismobjectivityphenomenologyrationalismrepresentationalismscienceskepticismsubjectivitythe clearingthe sensestruth

Next

» Polish-Style Territorial Defense Could Be the Answer to the Risk of Civil War in France

1 comment

  1. Baron Nishi says:
    May 25, 2021 at 4:53 pm

    This  concept of Erlichtung is so non-descript and insensate  that I don’t see how it can light up the intellectual interior of a matchbox let alone the space of human thought. Name an example of a human culture throughout the historical record had this “inveterate openness to Being” as Heidegger describes it, unless you consider ones whose way of life was very close to that of animals, such as the Aborigines. There was always some kind of “representation” as you term it, of the divine which animated mankind’s life of the spirit throughout the Ages. The more advanced a culture became, the more this “representation” of I should say, the ephemeral experience of the sublime and the eternal sought to crystallize itself, first in the realm of art, through myth, painting and allegorical poetry and finally in the realm of metaphysics, in terms of objective and universalizing human reason.

    I do not claim to be an expert on Heidegger, although I have read several of his more accessible works with great interest, particularly his lectures on pre-Socratic philosophy and criticism of modern technology. But based mostly on the fawning treatment he receives here and on other prominent outlets of dissident right opinion, I can glean that the gist of his philosophy lies in his attempt to transcend this position of extreme nominalism that he (and by extension the author of this article) took for granted. I never found this endeavor particularly convincing – the conclusions to which his thought led were more of a loosely described aesthetic vision than a clearly coherent philosophical argument, as such his modern adherents can’t help but interpret him on the basis of their own personal equations so to speak. I’ve seen as many readings of Heidegger as I had people who claimed to receive inspiration from him.

    To be quite honest, openness to such interpretative ambiguity seems to be Heidegger’s calling card. At the very least, to me, it appears the most logical that Heidegger was not a thinker of deep Antiquity as is commonly presented, but rather well within the Medieval tradition, specifically the branch of Germanic mysticism and its tendency to seek the truth in the ineffable and the obscured. He constantly sought to encapsulate the essence of the Medieval spirit unsullied by the rationalizations, presuppositions and cultural baggage of the contemporary theologians, who in spite of their pietous sounding language carried upon their tongues the putrid seed of unbelief.

    Which is incidentally why I agree with the general gist of your critique of the philosophical current of Traditionalism in the sense that the latter has little semblance with the actuality of a living tradition. The matter isn’t helped by the fact that most contemporary spokespersons of Traditionalism have a tendency to carry the reek of of New Age, ufological, Martinist and Theosophical currents of thought that rightly belong in the garbage bin of early 20th century intellectual fads.

    The subtle fault in this set of articles is that they presuppose that the ontological separation   from the divine is a given, inveterate state of human consciousness that has always persisted throughout history. Which is of course the exact same assumption that forms the basis of the exact same tradition that it claims to strive to divest itself from. The very statement that “metaphysical thinking is a pathology of the mind” implies an original sin that the human mind committed at some point of its cultural existence, which then formed, or more aptly, violated, the basis of all cultural and social life in ages past and present. We are supposed to take for granted that at some point of our cultural development, our collective mind dun goofed (was it the Christ thing? Or Plato? Or maybe before them, that whole story of  Greek Gods  toppling the Titans?) and not question the context in which such a profound error must have arisen – a signature mark of the intellectual sophomore, who in his conviction of the radicality of his propositions, forgets the crucial task of validating them in relation to the real world.

    Thus it clouds the question of human belief in the divine, and its cultural expression in the various religious forms, solely in terms of metaphysics, an intellectual privilege available a very very few educated persons. We are thus led to believe that every single human culture treated its relation to the higher realms of spirit in terms of what could be encapsulated within the boundaries of human reason and common experience. But this is clearly contradicted by much of the account of premodern history. The predominant spiritual discourse upon which Christianity is based was not Platonism as was in profound ignorance asserted in the first part of this article but matter of divinely revealed truth which was not the product of usual faculties of human reason. Neither were the divine agonies and ecstasies recollected in vivid detail in the writings of mystics such as St. Catherine of Siena, nor the profoundly unsettling spiritual epiphanies of highly learned men such Dante and Gregory Palamas. The stigmata, the visions, the towering cathedrals whose scope and majesty awes and terrifies in equal measure, the vestments, the images, the symbols of the faith, all of which were intended to evoke something far greater than the categories of human thought could achieve on their own. Even theology, properly understood, was explicitly distinct from mere metaphysical speculation, since at its core it’s closer to prophecy or theurgy than an intellectual discipline. The point is that none of this was seen as the product of discursive reason, nor its faculties of invention and imagination according to its own rubric of internal consistency.  Western spiritual tradition, rests on the premise of a synthesis of an enraptured human organism with the descending light of the eternal Spirit, a union between two separate modes of being normally inaccessible one another. Are we to assume that all of this was but a product of a mind twisted by erroneous thinking? Was it just all in their head? Are we supposed to take for granted the presupposition that every single recorded instance of the positive experience of the divine is nothing but the product of insanity and hallucination brought about by a wrong mental opinion about the nature of the non-existent supernatural world?

    All this hand-wrangling about which system of metaphysics is appropriate for the future palingenesis of our white civilization quite frankly strikes me as a sterile sort of discussion. Much as a same sex union can not produce legitimate offspring, no matter what legal or worse, surgical trick it resorts to, so can’t a post-modern philosophy based on radical subjective thinking replace the foundation of European society, of that which served as a basis for its ethical and legal systems, its art, poetry, works of literature and music throughout the millennia.  I’m not even arguing here from the perspective of defending the Christian religion, or even faith as such, or even in an attempt to “refute” nominalism and atheism of the modern era in so far as an ontological mood can be refuted. Rather I’m arguing here for the sake of the veracity of our history, in the sense that I refuse to accept as valid the notion that 2000 years of European experience of civilization  was predicated upon a  lie. To do so would be to reject the legitimacy of the unfolding process of Being itself, in an attempt to impose upon it one’s subjective will as a means to correct history’s perceived mistakes. But this is not a power that human beings inherently possess. Human beings can’t “ruin” history on an ontological level (I’m not speaking of economics and politics here) just as they can’t bring it back forth from ruin. It is the ultimate expression of the Faustian spirit, to turn to the Devil to undo what the Devil has wrought.

    Nobody of sound mind rejects the immanency of the diabolic in our society – all that is needed for a direct experience of it is to go outside while daring not to put on a face muzzle. Why is it so hard for one to comprehend the presence of the divine? Is this not why we have reason in the first place?

    0
    0

Comments are closed.

If you have Paywall access,
simply login first to see your comment auto-approved.

Note on comments privacy & moderation

Your email is never published nor shared.

Comments are moderated. If you don't see your comment, please be patient. If approved, it will appear here soon. Do not post your comment a second time.

  • Recent posts

    • Israel, Gaza, and the War for Your Mind

      Christian Secor

      1

    • Polish-Style Territorial Defense Could Be the Answer to the Risk of Civil War in France

      Olivier Bault

      1

    • Toward a New Spiritual Revolution

      Morris van de Camp

    • Introducing the Counter-Currents Book Club

      Greg Johnson

      1

    • The Fear of Writing

      Mark Gullick

    • Obi-Wan Kenobi

      Trevor Lynch

      1

    • The Homeland Institute’s Third Poll, Part Two: Is National Divorce a Solution?

      David M. Zsutty

    • Tommy Robinson: Fakta vs. emoce a nejnovější lži

      Huntley Haverstock

    • The Worst Week Yet: November 26-December 2, 2023

      Jim Goad

      10

    • Lamentations for a City

      Morris van de Camp

      6

    • The Homeland Institute’s Third Poll, Part One: American Democracy in Crisis

      David M. Zsutty

      1

    • Mike Johnson and Diff’rent Strokes: When Liberal Narratives Collapse

      Travis LeBlanc

      1

    • Using Politics to Segregate the Sexes

      Jim Goad

    • Imagine Jim Goad Singing “Imagine”

      Greg Johnson

      13

    • The Union Jackal, November 2023

      Mark Gullick

      5

    • Christmas Special: Merry Christmas, Infidels!

      Greg Johnson

      30

    • Jonathan Bowden’s The Cultured Thug

      Margot Metroland

      1

    • Le Manifeste Nationaliste Blanc: Introduction à un livre interdit

      Greg Johnson

    • Little Free Library Book Giveaway!

      Cyan Quinn

      5

    • Using Politics to Segregate the Sexes

      Jim Goad

      35

    • The Boondock Saints and Overnight: Troy Duffy’s Career as Cautionary Tale

      Travis LeBlanc

      6

    • David Zsutty Introduces the Homeland Institute: Transcript

      David M. Zsutty

    • It’s White Wednesday! Shop Our Sale Now

      Cyan Quinn

    • Ahsoka

      Trevor Lynch

      5

    • The US Military Excuses an Anti-White Massacre: Black Soldiers & the Houston Riot of 1917

      Dave Chambers

      2

    • “A Few More Steps and We Were . . . On Some Edge of Things”: Staircases That Lead Nowhere, Part 2

      Kathryn S.

      4

    • Counter-Currents Radio Podcast No. 561: An All-Star Thanksgiving Weekend Special

      Counter-Currents Radio

    • Giving Tuesday at Counter-Currents: Help Us Meet Our Match!

      Cyan Quinn

      5

    • “A Few More Steps and We Were . . . On Some Edge of Things”: Staircases That Lead Nowhere, Part 1

      Kathryn S.

      5

    • The Blacks Next Door

      Gunnar Alfredsson

      7

    • Where the Dissident Right Triumphs

      Lipton Matthews

      2

    • Used to Be a Bad Guy: Carlito’s Way at 30

      Mark Gullick

      3

    • The Worst Week Yet: November 19-25, 2023

      Jim Goad

      21

    • Ridley Scott’s Napoleon

      Trevor Lynch

      28

    • Are We (Finally) Living in the World of Atlas Shrugged? Part 2

      Jef Costello

      4

    • The Suppression of the Maryland Moderates During the Civil War

      Morris van de Camp

      2

    • The Anti-Black Plague “Black Death” of 1347-1351 Kills Half of Europe . . . Black Women Most Affected

      Jim Goad

      4

    • We Have Much to be Thankful For

      Greg Johnson

    • All-Star Thanksgiving Weekend Special!

      Greg Johnson

      2

    • Black Friday Special: It’s Time to STOP Shopping for Christmas

      Greg Johnson

      5

    • Are We (Finally) Living in the World of Atlas Shrugged? Part 1

      Jef Costello

      12

    • We Get the Crime We Deserve

      Spencer J. Quinn

      8

    • Nueva Derecha vs. Vieja Derecha, Capítulo 12: La Cuestión Cristiana en el Nacionalismo Blanco

      Greg Johnson

    • Happy Thanksgiving!

      Greg Johnson

      1

    • The Anti-Black Plague: “Black Death” of 1347-1351 Kills Half of Europe . . . Black Women Most Affected

      Jim Goad

      24

    • A Veteran’s Thanksgiving Message

      David M. Zsutty

      3

    • Horses and Heavy Hors d’Oeuvres

      James J. O'Meara

    • Let Elon Cook

      Travis LeBlanc

      3

    • Should We Defend Anti-Semitic Literature?

      Jason Kessler

      8

    • G. Gordon Liddy’s When I Was a Kid, This Was a Free Country, Part 2

      Beau Albrecht

  • Classics Corner

    • A Heroic Vision for Our Time: The Life and Ideas of Colin Wilson

      John Morgan

      12

    • Remembering J. Philippe Rushton (December 3, 1943–October 2, 2012)

      Greg Johnson

      7

    • Herman Husband, Eighteenth Century White Nationalist Pioneer

      Spencer J. Quinn

      10

    • Remembering Henry Williamson (December 1, 1895-August 13, 1977)

      Greg Johnson

    • Black Friday Special: It’s Time to STOP Shopping for Christmas

      Greg Johnson

      5

    • The Holy Mountain, Part 1

      Derek Hawthorne

      1

    • The Holy Mountain, Part 2

      Derek Hawthorne

      2

    • Remembering Krzysztof Penderecki (November 23, 1933-March 29, 2020)

      Alex Graham

    • Thanksgiving Day as a Harvest Festival

      Andrew Hamilton

    • Thanksgiving: The Only Holiday Unique to the American Ethny

      C. F. Robinson

      9

    • The Importance of Believing: Terry Pratchett’s Hogfather

      Howe Abbott-Hiss

      6

    • Remembering Madison Grant (November 19, 1865-May 30, 1937)

      Greg Johnson

      3

    • Remembering Wyndham Lewis (November 18, 1882-March 7, 1957)

      Greg Johnson

    • Remembering Sir Oswald Mosley (November 16, 1896-December 3, 1980)

      Greg Johnson

      4

    • Revolution of the Nation

      Sir Oswald Mosley

    • The Feminine Sexual Counter-Revolution and Its Limitations, Part 1

      F. Roger Devlin

      2

    • The Feminine Sexual Counter-Revolution and Its Limitations, Part 2

      F. Roger Devlin

      41

    • America and Israel: United in Struggle

      Alexander Jacob

      16

    • Zionism vs. White Nationalism

      Spencer J. Quinn

      7

    • Debate on Christianity

      Jonas De Geer and Greg Johnson

      42

    • In Defense of Populism

      Greg Johnson

      6

    • The Politics of Nuclear War, Part 3: Israel and the Bomb

      John Morgan

      30

    • For Leo Yankevich: October 30, 1961 to December 11, 2018

      Juleigh Howard-Hobson

      3

    • The Heresy of Christian Zionism: Israel, Christianity, & Genesis 12.2-3

      Irmin Vinson

      31

    • Philosemitism & Brutality

      Andrew Hamilton

      57

    • Charles Ives, American Composer

      Alex Graham

      8

    • Remembering Friedrich Nietzsche
      (October 15, 1844–August 25, 1900)

      Greg Johnson

      5

    • Remembering Aleister Crowley (October 12, 1875–December 1, 1947)

      Greg Johnson

      10

    • Remembering Ralph Vaughan Williams (October 12, 1872–August 26, 1958)

      Alex Graham

      3

    • Archeofuturist Fiction: Frank Herbert’s Dune

      Greg Johnson

      23

  • Paroled from the Paywall

    • Never the Twain: Notes on Logic and Morality

      Mark Gullick

      18

    • Counter-Currents Radio Podcast No. 557: New Ask Me Anything with Greg Johnson

      Counter-Currents Radio

      3

    • Heil Honey, I’m Home

      Travis LeBlanc

      2

    • Management and Working Remotely

      Morris van de Camp

      1

    • The Protocols of Zion Today, Part 2

      Beau Albrecht

    • The Protocols of Zion Today, Part 1

      Beau Albrecht

      8

    • The Rise and Fall of Ibram X. Kendi

      Beau Albrecht

      14

    • Remembering the Great White Hopes of Boxing

      Travis LeBlanc

      10

    • Race and IQ Differences: An Interview with Arthur Jensen, Part 5

      Arthur Jensen

    • Nueva Derecha vs. Vieja Derecha Capítulo 10: El Peso de Hitler

      Greg Johnson

    • Gerald P. Nye: American Patriot and Midwestern Isolationist, Part 2

      Morris van de Camp

    • Gerald P. Nye: American Patriot and Midwestern Isolationist, Part 1

      Morris van de Camp

    • Looking for Mr. Goodbar: A Tale of Disco-Era Debauchery

      Travis LeBlanc

      26

    • Race & IQ Differences: An Interview with Arthur Jensen, Part 4

      Arthur Jensen

    • For Lesbians Only

      Beau Albrecht

      11

    • Why Cartoons Have Potential: A Response to Travis LeBlanc, Part 2

      White Lion Movement

    • Fictionalizing the Right

      Clarissa Schnabel

      5

    • Jack Hinson’s One-Man War

      Spencer J. Quinn

      2

    • The 12 Black Years Since Jared Taylor’s White Identity

      Mark Gullick

      4

    • Exercise Tips for the Anxious

      Gunnar Alfredsson

      3

    • Race & IQ Differences: An Interview with Arthur Jensen, Part 3

      Arthur Jensen

    • It’s Not All About You

      Spencer J. Quinn

      5

    • Counter-Currents Radio Podcast No. 554 How Often Does Pox Think About the Roman Empire? . . . & Other Matters

      Counter-Currents Radio

    • White Altruism Revealed

      Gunnar Alfredsson

      2

    • The Matter with Concrete, Part 2

      Michael Walker

      2

    • The Matter with Concrete, Part 1

      Michael Walker

      4

    • The Captivity Narrative of Fanny Kelly

      Spencer J. Quinn

      11

    • Race and IQ Differences: An Interview with Arthur Jensen, Part 2

      Arthur Jensen

      3

    • The Unnecessary War

      Morris van de Camp

      3

    • Marx vs. Rousseau

      Stephen Paul Foster

      4

  • Recent comments

    • ArminiusMaximus

      Israel, Gaza, and the War for Your Mind

      Beautifully written. The ending is a perfect summation of the core issue at hand. In the spirit of...

    • Gallus

      Polish-Style Territorial Defense Could Be the Answer to the Risk of Civil War in France

      Great piece of writing contrasting the very real threat that has engulfed towns, cities and could...

    • MC

      Introducing the Counter-Currents Book Club

      Love this

    • nineofclubs

      The Worst Week Yet: November 26-December 2, 2023

      Obregon’s mother may lack certain social graces, but it must be said that her venom - directed at...

    • Kathryn S

      “A Few More Steps and We Were . . . On Some Edge of Things”: Staircases That Lead Nowhere, Part 1

      Wow, what a neat assignment! And that's an interesting observation about the Alpine villagers and...

    • Beau Albrecht

      The Stolen Land Narrative

      That sounds like something that Howard Zinn would come up with, a lying activist pretending to be a...

    • Beau Albrecht

      Obi-Wan Kenobi

      Whew... As Anakin Skywalker once said:  "Noooooooooooooooooooooo!"

    • Alexandra O.

      The Homeland Institute’s Third Poll, Part One: American Democracy in Crisis

      I think that most White people find it easier to get along with others of another political...

    • Will Williams

      Christmas Special: Merry Christmas, Infidels!

      Greg: Kwanzaa is supposed to be a Negro alternative to Christmas. It is a seven-day feast,...

    • Richard Smith

      Imagine Jim Goad Singing “Imagine”

      First time I heard Jim singing "White Room" above, it's damn good!

    • Josephus Cato

      The Worst Week Yet: November 26-December 2, 2023

      I was hoping he would have succeeded in his appeal to SCOTUS.  I'm wondering if it was declined due...

    • DarkPlato

      Lamentations for a City

      I’ll wager Bovarian Motor Works has a large percentage of it by now!

    • Gallus

      Lamentations for a City

      That was a superb article. Thanks for sharing the link to the documentary, I shall watch that with...

    • Fyrdman

      Christmas Special: Merry Christmas, Infidels!

      Interesting article, with interesting reader responses. Here in England, the mercantile Christmas tv...

    • Hamburger Today

      Christmas Special: Merry Christmas, Infidels!

      The 'divine mother and child' is a pre-Christian tableu.Innana, the ‘mother’ figure in the Egyptian...

    • ncleapyear

      Lamentations for a City

      I read somewhere that George Wallace referred to Humphrey as a "pointy head" in the 1968...

    • Kök Böri

      The Worst Week Yet: November 26-December 2, 2023

      Тurscak is either an Ukrainian, or a Pole.

    • DarkPlato

      Lamentations for a City

      Great article. Of course it was all to get whites back for electing Trump. As were the Covid...

    • Fire Walk With Lee

      The Worst Week Yet: November 26-December 2, 2023

      Victims of black on white violence are just experiencing diversity.  Or experiencing cultural...

    • Anne Frank Rizzo

      The Worst Week Yet: November 26-December 2, 2023

      Not only has the Mexican Mafia had white members https://en.m.wikipedia.org/wiki/Joe_%22Pegleg%...

  • Book Authors

    • Beau Albrecht
    • Alain de Benoist
    • Kerry Bolton
    • Jonathan Bowden
    • Collin Cleary
    • Jef Costello
    • Savitri Devi
    • F. Roger Devlin
    • Buttercup Dew
    • Julius Evola
    • Jim Goad
    • Gregory Hood
    • Juleigh Howard-Hobson
    • Greg Johnson
    • Charles Krafft
    • Anthony M. Ludovici
    • Trevor Lynch
    • H. L. Mencken
    • J. A. Nicholl
    • James J. O’Meara
    • Christopher Pankhurst
    • Tito Perdue
    • Michael Polignano
    • Spencer J. Quinn
    • Fenek Solère
    • Irmin Vinson
    • Leo Yankevich
    • Francis Parker Yockey
    • Multiple authors
  • Webzine Authors

    Editor-in-Chief

    • Greg Johnson, Ph.D.

    Featured Writers

    • Beau Albrecht
    • Morris V. de Camp
    • Stephen Paul Foster, Ph.D.
    • Jim Goad
    • Alex Graham
    • Mark Gullick, Ph.D.
    • Greg Johnson, Ph.D.
    • Spencer J. Quinn

    Frequent Writers

    • Aquilonius
    • Anthony Bavaria
    • Alain de Benoist
    • Kerry Bolton, Ph.D.
    • Collin Cleary, Ph.D.
    • Jef Costello
    • F. Roger Devlin, Ph.D.
    • Richard Houck
    • Ondrej Mann
    • Margot Metroland
    • John Morgan
    • Trevor Lynch
    • James J. O’Meara
    • Kathryn S.
    • Thomas Steuben
    • Michael Walker

    Classic Authors

    • Maurice Bardèche
    • Jonathan Bowden
    • Julius Evola
    • Guillaume Faye
    • Ernst Jünger
    • Kevin MacDonald, Ph.D.
    • D. H. Lawrence
    • Charles Lindbergh
    • Jack London
    • H. P. Lovecraft
    • Anthony M. Ludovici
    • Sir Oswald Mosley
    • National Vanguard
    • Friedrich Nietzsche
    • Revilo Oliver
    • William Pierce
    • Ezra Pound
    • Saint-Loup
    • Savitri Devi
    • Carl Schmitt
    • Miguel Serrano
    • Oswald Spengler
    • P. R. Stephensen
    • Jean Thiriart
    • John Tyndall
    • Dominique Venner
    • Leo Yankevich
    • Francis Parker Yockey

    Other Authors

    • Howe Abbott-Hiss
    • Michael Bell
    • Buttercup Dew
    • Giles Corey
    • Bain Dewitt
    • Jack Donovan
    • Richardo Duchesne, Ph.D.
    • Emile Durand
    • Guillaume Durocher
    • Mark Dyal
    • Fullmoon Ancestry
    • Tom Goodroch
    • Andrew Hamilton
    • Robert Hampton
    • Huntley Haverstock
    • Derek Hawthorne
    • Gregory Hood
    • Juleigh Howard-Hobson
    • Alexander Jacob
    • Nicholas Jeelvy
    • Ruuben Kaalep
    • Tobias Langdon
    • Julian Langness
    • Travis LeBlanc
    • Patrick Le Brun
    • G A Malvicini
    • John Michael McCloughlin
    • Millennial Woes
    • Michael O’Meara
    • Christopher Pankhurst
    • Michael Polignano
    • J. J. Przybylski
    • Quintilian
    • Edouard Rix
    • C. B. Robertson
    • C. F. Robinson
    • Herve Ryssen
    • Alan Smithee
    • Fenek Solere
    • Ann Sterzinger
    • Robert Steuckers
    • Tomislav Sunic
    • Donald Thoresen
    • Marian Van Court
    • Irmin Vinson
    • Aylmer Wedgwood
    • Scott Weisswald
  • Departments

    • Book Reviews
    • Movie Reviews
    • TV Reviews
    • Music Reviews
    • Art Criticism
    • Graphic Novels & Comics
    • Video Game Reviews
    • Fiction
    • Poems
    • Interviews
    • Videos
    • English Translations
    • Other Languages
      • Arabic
      • Bulgarian
      • Croatian
      • Czech
      • Danish
      • Dutch
      • Estonian
      • Finnish
      • French
      • German
      • Greek
      • Hungarian
      • Italian
      • Lithuanian
      • Norwegian
      • Polish
      • Portuguese
      • Romanian
      • Russian
      • Slovak
      • Spanish
      • Swedish
      • Ukrainian
    • Commemorations
    • Why We Write
  • Archives
  • Top 100 Commenters
Sponsored Links
Spencer J. Quinn CC Giving Tuesday Above Time Coffee Antelope Hill Publishing Paul Waggener IHR-Store American Renaissance Jim Goad The Occidental Observer
Donate Now Mailing list
Books for sale
  • The Cultured Thug
  • Opportunities in Alabama Agriculture
  • Toward a New Nationalism
  • The Trial of Socrates
  • Fields of Asphodel
  • El Manifiesto Nacionalista Blanco
  • An Artist of the Right
  • Ernst Jünger
  • Reuben
  • The Partisan
  • Trevor Lynch’s Classics of Right-Wing Cinema
  • The Enemy of Europe
  • Imperium
  • Reactionary Modernism
  • Manifesto del Nazionalismo Bianco
  • O Manifesto Nacionalista Branco
  • Vade Mecum
  • Whiteness: The Original Sin
  • Space Vixen Trek Episode 17: Tomorrow the Stars
  • The Year America Died
  • Passing the Buck
  • Mysticism After Modernism
  • Gold in the Furnace
  • Defiance
  • Forever & Ever
  • Wagner’s Ring & the Germanic Tradition
  • Resistance
  • Materials for All Future Historians
  • Love Song of the Australopiths
  • White Identity Politics
  • Here’s the Thing
  • Trevor Lynch: Part Four of the Trilogy
  • Graduate School with Heidegger
  • It’s Okay to Be White
  • The World in Flames
  • The White Nationalist Manifesto
  • From Plato to Postmodernism
  • The Gizmo
  • Return of the Son of Trevor Lynch’s CENSORED Guide to the Movies
  • Toward a New Nationalism
  • The Smut Book
  • The Alternative Right
  • My Nationalist Pony
  • Dark Right: Batman Viewed From the Right
  • The Philatelist
  • Confessions of an Anti-Feminist
  • East and West
  • Though We Be Dead, Yet Our Day Will Come
  • White Like You
  • Numinous Machines
  • Venus and Her Thugs
  • Cynosura
  • North American New Right, vol. 2
  • You Asked For It
  • More Artists of the Right
  • Extremists: Studies in Metapolitics
  • The Homo & the Negro
  • Rising
  • The Importance of James Bond
  • In Defense of Prejudice
  • Confessions of a Reluctant Hater (2nd ed.)
  • The Hypocrisies of Heaven
  • Waking Up from the American Dream
  • Green Nazis in Space!
  • Truth, Justice, and a Nice White Country
  • Heidegger in Chicago
  • End of an Era: Mad Men & the Ordeal of Civility
  • Sexual Utopia in Power
  • What is a Rune? & Other Essays
  • Son of Trevor Lynch’s White Nationalist Guide to the Movies
  • The Lightning & the Sun
  • The Eldritch Evola
  • Western Civilization Bites Back
  • New Right vs. Old Right
  • Journey Late at Night: Poems and Translations
  • The Non-Hindu Indians & Indian Unity
  • I do not belong to the Baader-Meinhof Group
  • Pulp Fascism
  • The Lost Philosopher
  • Trevor Lynch’s A White Nationalist Guide to the Movies
  • And Time Rolls On
  • Artists of the Right: Resisting Decadence
  • North American New Right, Vol. 1
  • Some Thoughts on Hitler
  • Tikkun Olam and Other Poems
  • Summoning the Gods
  • Taking Our Own Side
  • Reuben
  • The Node
  • The New Austerities
  • Morning Crafts
  • The Passing of a Profit & Other Forgotten Stories
Copyright © 2023 Counter-Currents Publishing, Ltd.

Paywall Access





Please enter your email address.

Lost your password?

Edit your comment