Leo Strauss, the Conservative Revolution, & National Socialism, Part 3
Greg Johnson3,373 words
Part 3 of 3 (Part 1 here, Part 2 here)
Editor’s Note:
In the previous installment of this series, I examined Leo Strauss’s argument that the roots of what he called “German nihilism” — including National Socialism — were not nihilistic. Instead, it is rooted in a moral critique of the modern world. In this installment, I examine his argument that these non-nihilistic motives gave rise to nihilism because of certain contingent historical circumstances.
2. The Contingent Emergence of German Nihilism
The second part of “German Nihilism” comprises three sub-sections numbered 4, 5, and 6. Strauss begins his account of the circumstances that led to German nihilism with a provisional definition: “Let me tentatively define nihilism as the desire to destroy the present world and its potentialities, a desire not accompanied by any clear conception of what one wants to put in its place” (p. 359).
Strauss, moreover, makes it clear that he is not trying to explain Hitler’s worldview. Nor is he trying to explain why the German masses supported Hitler. Instead, Strauss is exclusively concerned with why a certain number of “very intelligent” and “very decent” college-educated “young men”—who obviously formed only a tiny percentage of the German population—came to support National Socialism.
Strauss claims that he totally lacks “the gift of a lyrical reporter” necessary to communicate the emotions underlying German nihilism, but this is false modesty, since Strauss’s portrait of the young men who moved from the Conservative Revolution to National Socialism is quite vivid. William Altman suggests that it is Strauss’s self-portrait, which is true only insofar as Strauss himself was influenced by the Conservative Revolutionary milieu, but I reject Altman’s claim that Strauss was an actual Jewish Nazi.[1]
Strauss concedes that the liberal democracy of the Weimar Republic was totally inadequate. There were only two “articulate alternatives”: reaction and Communism (p. 359). Communism was “more interesting” to intellectuals. But the Communist vision of society filled nobler souls with dread:
. . . a rising of the proletariat and of the proletarianized strata of society which would usher in the withering away of the State, the classless society, the abolition of all exploitation and injustice, the era of final peace. It was this prospect at least as much as the desperate present, which led to nihilism. The prospect of a pacified planet, without rulers and ruled, of a planetary society devoted to production and consumption only, to the production and consumption of spiritual as well as material merchandise, was positively horrifying to quite a few very intelligent and very decent, if very young, Germans. (pp. 359–60)
Strauss emphasizes that the objection to Marxism was not based on “economic and social position” since “they no longer had anything to lose.” Nor was the objection religious, since his subjects were atheists of the Right. (College-educated, non-bourgeois, Right-wing atheists: it becomes clear just what a tiny percentage of the population Strauss is really discussing.) Instead, their objection is based on a non-religious, aristocratic moral outlook heavily influenced by Nietzsche, to whom Strauss alludes below:
What they hated, was the very prospect of a world in which everyone would be happy and satisfied, in which everyone would have his little pleasure by day and his little pleasure by night, a world in which no great heart could beat and no great soul could breathe, a world without real, unmetaphoric, sacrifice, i.e., a world without blood, sweat, and tears. What to the communists appeared to be the fulfilment of the dream of mankind, appeared to those young Germans as the greatest debasement of humanity, as the coming of the end of humanity, as the arrival of [Nietzsche’s] the latest man. (p. 360)
Strauss claims that these young men had no positive alternative to communism. They had a “no” but not a “yes,” therefore, they could only work to destroy, not create. This, for Strauss, is the meaning of German nihilism.
Thus far Strauss has merely restated his definition of German nihilism without explaining how it went wrong and led to support to National Socialism. But already we can see that, on Strauss’s definition, National Socialism was not mere nihilism. Yes, Hitler wished to destroy Communism, liberal democracy, and social decadence. Yes, he wished to overturn the Treaty of Versailles. But these were just means to a range of positive goals that were quite clearly envisioned. Hitler wanted to unite the scattered German populations into a modern, technological society defined in racial rather than cultural terms (i.e., culturally German Jews are not Germans). He abolished liberal-democratic party politics, which had brought Germany to the brink of ruin, creating a one party state. But he maintained universal suffrage and sought to replace hierarchies based on birth and money with one based on merit. He sought to raise the living and health standards of the masses, abolish child labor, increase wages and leisure time for workers, improve industry and agriculture, build infrastructure, protect nature, foster the arts and culture, and build magnificent monuments, buildings, and urban spaces—all of which required conditions of peace, not war. The most basic positive goals of National Socialism were outlined by Hitler in 1920 in a very specific 25-point political platform,[2] but his constructive ambitions grew after he attained political power: everything from providing warm winter clothes to the poor to rebuilding the cores of Berlin and Linz. Hitler, moreover, did not keep his programs secret. He was very effective in communicating them to the masses. Therefore, anyone in Germany in the 1920s and 1930s could easily determine Hitler’s positive goals.
There may, of course, have been people who shared National Socialism’s negative goals but not its positive ones, or any positive ones, for that matter. But that says nothing about the nature of National Socialism. It merely shows that some people supported a non-nihilistic political movement out of nihilistic motives.
Furthermore, the desire to smash an evil social system without proposing a clear alternative is not necessarily nihilism. Having no idea of what will come next is not the same as wanting nothing to come next. Instead, it may simply reflect realism: it is always easier to destroy than to create. It may also reflect a sense of the limits of the power to plan for the future and a faith in the potential for social self-organization. Strauss’s objection, by contrast, betrays a prejudice in favor of what F. A. Hayek called “constructivist rationalism,” i.e., the idea that one can intentionally construct social orders as opposed to merely clear away the impediments to natural processes of social self-organization.
Strauss, of course, never mentions the real reason why he opposed Hitler. Strauss opposed Hitler not because he wished to destroy the modern world. Hitler actually embraced much of modernity but sought to place it on heroic-aristocratic rather than bourgeois moral foundations, which was not all that different from Strauss’s project of placing a socially conservative “liberal democracy” on the foundations of a spiritual aristocracy.
No, Strauss opposed Hitler simply because he destroyed Jewish power in Germany. Indeed, that was really Strauss’s only fundamental objection to Hitler. In “German Nihilism,” Strauss’s one remark on the Jewish question is: “Their anti-Jewish policy does seem to be taken seriously by the Nazis” (p. 368). Not exactly his finest hour as a political observer.
But what is Strauss’s account of the contingent situation that led German nihilists to embrace National Socialism? Strauss’s analysis turns out to be quite thin.
First, he suggests that some embraced nihilism because they accepted the false premise that communism is the culmination of civilization and thus decided to dispense with civilization rather than embrace communism (p. 360).
Second, he suggests that there is a natural affinity of youth to nihilism, and Germany, which was burdened both with “progressive education” and mealy-mouthed conservatism, lacked the “old-fashioned” and yet “undogmatic” teachers necessary to talk their students out of such notions (p. 361). Such teachers would have to “understand the ardent passion underlying the negation of the present world and its potentialities.” They would have to be able to “explain to [the youth] in articulate language the positive, and not merely destructive, meaning of their aspirations,” (p. 362). And who better to do that than someone who once shared those passions and aspirations but then thought his way beyond them? A teacher like Leo Strauss, for instance.
Third, in Germany at the time, young people were empowered to make bad political decisions (p. 361).
Fourth, instead of finding a teacher like Strauss, the young men in question encountered the Conservative Revolutionaries, the “group of professors and writers who knowingly or ignorantly paved the way for Hitler (Spengler, Moeller van den Bruck, Carl Schmitt, Bäumler, Ernst Jünger, Heidegger)” (p. 362).
Finally, Strauss offers the absurd suggestion that everything could have been turned around if the young men in question could have heard the rhetoric of Churchill rather than Hitler, since Churchill calls upon sublime emotions in the defense of “civilization”—by which Strauss means the British Empire and the broader Anglosphere, which were characterized by extreme openness to Jews and (consequently) extreme hostility to National Socialism (p. 363). Since Strauss himself was quite impressed with Churchill, this counts in favor of the semi-autobiographical nature of the portrait he creates.
But there is also, surely, an autobiographical—or at least aspirational—aspect to Strauss’s portrait of the teacher who could have taken a fundamental Right-wing critique of the modern world and deflected it from National Socialist—and, more to the point, anti-Semitic—political commitments. Indeed, I would argue that we are witnessing here the genesis of what Paul Gotttfried identifies as Strauss’s intellectual and educational agenda: to channel the Right-wing critique of modernity away from any form of anti-Semitic ethnonationalism.[3] (Jewish ethnonationalism, i.e., Zionism, is just fine, however.)
Another theme of the mature Strauss, namely the bane of historicism, can be glimpsed through a verbal mist in sub-section 6, which Strauss labels in his outline, “On the affinity of progressivism to nihilism: progressivism leaves the aim undefined; it therefore opposes an indefinite No to the given order” (p. 356). Here Strauss urges his audience to imaginatively enter into the German nihilist point of view. He then constructs a German nihilist persona and position that would be maximally seductive to his New School audience.[4]
“Nihilism,” they would say, is a slogan used by those who do not understand the new, who see merely the rejection of their cherished ideals, the destruction of their spiritual property, who judge the new by its first words and deeds, which are, of necessity, a caricature rather than an adequate expression. [This is, among other things, a witheringly accurate description of Rauschning’s use of “nihilism.”] How can a reasonable man expect an adequate expression of the ideal of a new epoch at its beginning, considering that the owl of Minerva starts its flight when the sun is setting? (p. 363)
In his Philosophy of Right, Hegel argues that history cannot be understood while it is being made. We cannot see and understand events when we are in their midst. And we cannot predict the future. History can only be understood retrospectively, when it is complete. Then we can look back at it and see the patterns that elude us in the whirl of events. He summed this view up with the metaphor of the owl of Minerva, the totem animal of the goddess of wisdom, who takes flight only at dusk, i.e., at the end of the day, when the work of making history is complete and its products can be surveyed and understood.
Strauss’s imagined nihilist then casts away the baggage of Hitler and National Socialism, dismissing them as vulgar and ephemeral. But he reaffirms the Right-wing critique of modernity that he shares with the Nazis. In truth, Strauss’s gambit of rejecting National Socialism specifically while affirming its broader Conservative Revolutionary genus is not so different from the European New Right.
The Nazis? Hitler? The less is said about him, the better. He will soon be forgotten. He is merely the rather contemptible tool of “History”: the midwife who assists at the birth of the new epoch, of a new spirit; and a midwife usually understands nothing of the genius at whose birth she assists; she is not even supposed to be a competent gynaecologist. A new reality is in the making; it is transforming the whole world; in the meantime there is: nothing, but a fertile nothing. The Nazis are as unsubstantial as clouds; the sky is hidden at present by those clouds which announce a devastating storm, but at the same time the long-needed rain which will bring new life to the dried up soil; and (here I am almost quoting) do not lose hope; what appears to you the end of the world, is merely the end of an epoch, of the epoch which began in 1517 or so. (pp. 363–64)
The epoch which began in “1517 or so” is the modern age: 1517 is the year Luther published his 95 Theses, and the “or so” might reach back to 1513 when Machiavelli first started circulating the manuscript of The Prince, a work of epochal importance according to Strauss. (The Prince was published posthumously in 1532, which might also fall into the ambit of Strauss’s “or so.”)
Then Strauss springs his trap. I think it is reasonable to assume that Strauss’s audience consisted of men who were sympathetic to historicism, in either its moderate progressive or radical Heideggerian versions. Thus they were probably discomfited by Strauss’s assertion that historicism is one of the reasons for the triumph of National Socialism, by encouraging outright acceptance as well as weak resistance to it:
I frankly confess, I do not see how those can resist the voice of that siren [Strauss’ feigned German nihilist] who expect the answer to the first and the last question from “History,” from the future as such; who mistake analysis of the present or past or future for philosophy; who believe in a progress toward a goal which is itself progressive and therefore undefinable; who are not guided by a known and stable standard: by a standard which is stable and not changeable, and which is known and not merely believed. In other words, the lack of resistance to nihilism seems to be due ultimately to the depreciation and the contempt of reason, which is one and unchangeable or it is not, and of science. For if reason is changeable, it is dependent on those forces which cause its changes; it is a servant and slave of the emotions; and it will be hard to make a distinction, which is not arbitrary, between noble and base emotions, once one has denied the rulership of reason. A German who could boast of a life-long intimate intercourse with the superhuman father of all nihilism, has informed us as reliably, as we were ever informed by any inspired author, that the originator of all nihilism admitted: “Just despise reason and science, the very highest power of man, and I have got you completely.” (p. 364)
The German Strauss mentions is Goethe’s Faust, and the “superhuman father of all nihilism” is Mephistopheles himself.[5] Strauss mentions historicism again in sub-section 8 the essay:
If nihilism is the rejection of the principles of civilization as such, and if civilization is based on recognition of the fact that the subject of civilization is man as man, every interpretation of science and morals in terms of races, or of nations, or of cultures, is strictly speaking nihilistic. Whoever accepts the idea of a Nordic or German or Faustic science, e.g., rejects eo ipso the idea of science. Different “cultures” may have produced different types of “science”; but only one of them can be true, can be science. (p. 366)
Strauss’s reference to “Faustic” science alludes to Oswald Spengler’s philosophy of history, which advances a radical cultural relativism which claims that different high cultures not only have distinct arts and religions, but different sciences as well.
The aim of reason is to discover truths about objective reality. The sciences are just reason applied to the investigation of different realms of objective reality. Objective reality is the same for all people, so the truths discovered by reason are universal.
Cultural and historical relativism denies the universality of truth claims, insisting that there are different truths for different ages and different cultures. If objective reality is one, then a plurality of culturally distinct “truths” are not objective. Reason is unable to reach objective and universal truths because it is conditioned by and dependent upon pre-rational and non-rational forces such as language and culture, which are the mutable products of historical contingencies. Reason, therefore, cannot be our master. It can only be the servant of pre-rational forces and commitments, particularly our ethnic identities.
According to Strauss, objective and universal truths are foundations of civilization. Although Strauss does not say it, this would invest civilization with a universalist and thus crusading and globalizing impetus. Thus the denial of objective truth attacks civilization at its foundations. And since for Strauss, “Nihilism is the rejection of the principles of civilization as such” (p. 364), relativism is nihilism, or a form of nihilism.
Strauss calls such relativism “historicism” and, in his own version of the reductio ad Hitlerum, warns that it paved the way for Hitler. In the case of Heidegger, this is true. But Spengler’s similarly radical historicism did not lead him to support the Third Reich, perhaps because Spengler himself was only three quarters German and one quarter Jewish. And of course the vast majority of Hitler’s followers were not influenced by the arcana of philosophical historicism.
But recall that Strauss’s main focus is on the college educated. And with this population, Strauss has a point: if one accepts a radical Heideggerian form of historicism—if one owns up to one’s debts to one’s language, culture, and nation, which constitute one’s identity before one is old enough to exercise the power of reason—and if one honors those debts, not by paying them back (which is impossible) but by paying them forward, i.e., by perpetuating one’s heritage into the future—then one will arrive at a form of traditionalist, collectivist, and illiberal nationalism like National Socialism.
As a Jew, Strauss felt threatened by this form of nationalism (when practiced by gentiles), and having settled in the United States, he was determined to insure that it did not take root there as well. Thus Strauss’s mature philosophical, political, and educational project came into focus. For the rest of his career, he worked to turn the American Right away from all forms of historicism and toward classical political philosophy, which is characterized by the rational pursuit of universal, objective truths. (For more details on this project, see my review of Paul Gottfried’s Leo Strauss and the Conservative Movement in America.[6])
Yet the question remains: was Strauss’ conversion from historicism to a kind of absolutism sincere or merely feigned? Did Strauss remain a historicist and, by his own definition, a nihilist? If so, then his critique of historicism is merely an expression of his own historical situatedness, i.e., that of a diaspora Jew who sought to promote the safety and success of his people by teaching a form of moral universalism that guaranteed their citizenship and social mobility. One cannot answer this question without a careful analysis of Strauss’s critiques of historicism. But the fact that Strauss maintained a lifelong commitment to his Jewish identity leads one to suspect that it was not reason but his own historical situatedness that had the final word.
Notes
1. William H. F. Altman, The German Stranger: Leo Strauss and National Socialism (Lanham, M.D.: Lexington Books, 2011), p. 301.
2. http://avalon.law.yale.edu/imt/nsdappro.asp
3. Paul Edward Gottfried, Leo Strauss and the Conservative Movement in America: A Critical Appraisal (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2012), p. 120. See also my review: https://counter-currents.com/2014/01/paul-gottfrieds-leo-strauss-the-conservative-movement-in-america/
4. According to Eugene R. Sheppard, the New School’s study group on the “German Problem” included: “Eduard Heinemann (economist), Erich Hula (political scientist), Karl Mayer (sociologist), Albert Salomon (sociologist), Kurt Riezler (philosopher), Horace Kallen (philosopher and psychologist), and Felix Kaufmann (philosopher).” Eugene R. Sheppard, Leo Strauss and the Politics of Exile: The Making of a Political Philosopher (Waltham, Mass: Brandeis University Press, 2006), p. 96. Salomon, Kallen, and Kaufmann were Jewish. Kurt Riezler was German but philo-Semitic and anti-Nazi. I have not been able to determine the ethnicity of Heinemann, Hula, and Mayer.
5. The quote from Mephistopheles is from Goethe, Faust, Part I, 1851–55.
Leo%20Strauss%2C%20the%20Conservative%20Revolution%2C%20and%23038%3B%20National%20Socialism%2C%20Part%203
Share
Enjoyed this article?
Be the first to leave a tip in the jar!
* * *
Counter-Currents has extended special privileges to those who donate at least $10/month or $120/year.
- Donors will have immediate access to all Counter-Currents posts. Everyone else will find that one post a day, five posts a week will be behind a “paywall” and will be available to the general public after 30 days. Naturally, we do not grant permission to other websites to repost paywall content before 30 days have passed.
- Paywall member comments will appear immediately instead of waiting in a moderation queue. (People who abuse this privilege will lose it.)
- Paywall members have the option of editing their comments.
- Paywall members get an Badge badge on their comments.
- Paywall members can “like” comments.
- Paywall members can “commission” a yearly article from Counter-Currents. Just send a question that you’d like to have discussed to [email protected]. (Obviously, the topics must be suitable to Counter-Currents and its broader project, as well as the interests and expertise of our writers.)
To get full access to all content behind the paywall, please visit our redesigned Paywall page.
Related
-
Unmourned Funeral: Chapter 9
-
Remembering Frank Herbert: October 8, 1920–February 11, 1986
-
Counter-Currents Radio Podcast No. 609: Ask Me Anything with Greg Johnson
-
Heidegger, Schelling, and the Reality of Evil
-
Unmourned Funeral: Chapter 8
-
Remembering Savitri Devi (September 30, 1905–October 22, 1982)
-
Heidegger, Schelling, and the Reality of Evil
-
Will America Survive to 2040?
13 comments
Yes, quite. This was exactly the point I tried to make to Prof Shadia Drury, & that was before I had a Rightist bone in my body. I haven’t read the Altman book but I would now describe Strauss as a ‘Jewish nazi’, depending on how we define our terms. At last the truth is out about Strauss.
Thanks for this. For a while I did not want to read anything written by a Jew because I was so angry at how they had distorted so much white history and I did not know how they had done it. But, I am getting wiser and I think it is very important to know how they think and how they convince others of their righteousness. I know all Jews are not out to get Whites, but it is very subtle and when push comes shove everyone chooses. I also think the exoteric and esoteric has not been made more explicit to whites for a number of reasons. I think a lot of it stems from our idea of individualism and letting sleeping dogs lie and of course who is seeking it(knowledge) out which we are not encouraged to do. I do so appreciate this site as I am forced to think about things that my laziness (sloth) would rather not confront.
I am also reminded of something Gregory Hood said at Radix about rationalizing the irrational and I thought yes, we often forget to remember the first assumption in an exposition and follow along like sheep.
I wan to ask about something in the last post. Johnson writes “Thus to open one’s horizons to other cultures, one must first reflect on one’s own culture. But reflection is incompatible with participation: one either plays the game or is a spectator, but one cannot be both.”
So Strauss, Nietzsche, etc. favored “closed cultures” where people do not reflect on their own cultures or those of other people. My question is how is such a world created, especially given modern technology? How do you prevent people from traveling, reading stuff on the internet, etc.? Even telling people “Don’t reflect on your culture” causes one to reflect on it. In other words, isn’t Strauss worldview impossible to realize without extreme repression?
These are good questions. One can’t prevent reflection, cross-cultural contact, etc. But there are two ways one can “manage” them. One is to inoculate people against the enervating effects of opened horizons by implanting a strong sense of ethic identity and pride from a young age. A good liberal education can then temper that core of identity — making it flexible rather than brittle in its encounters with other outlooks and ways of life. Beyond that, there is a third possibility alongside unreflective rootedness and deracinating reflection, and that is a reflective return to one’s origins with renewed appreciation and commitment.
[. . .] Why don’t we see more articles about Hegel around here?
We do deal with Hegel, although of course we could also do better. See the following articles tagged G. W. F. Hegel: https://counter-currents.com/tag/g-w-f-hegel/
“…if civilization is based on recognition of the fact that the subject of civilization is man as man, every interpretation of science and morals in terms of races, or of nations, or of cultures, is strictly speaking nihilistic.”
Strauss’ phrase “man as man” refers, of course, to human nature, which presupposes a fixed, knowable essence upon which the science of “living in the city” can be based. For Strauss, this notion derived from Aristotle’s understanding of human nature as “rational”, along with a subsequent Thomist (Christian) synthesis where the formal aspect of the human “substance” determines the material aspect.
However, we must realize that in Aristotle’s time, and also in the Middle Ages, the knowledge of “men”, and hence of man’s nature, was quite limited. Aristotle did not know much about Jews, Chinese, Africans, and so forth. Mexicans had not yet been invented. Neither did St. Thomas (although Aquinas was more familiar with Jews, and, it must be said, was generally not very happy about their traits–traits which, for him, were a theological problem). In other words, everyone anyone probably encountered was more European than not. In such a world it made sense to speak of a common human nature. To do so now is a mistake, and a univocal conception of nature necessarily leads to wrong conclusions.
Finally, it is clear that Strauss relies on Carl Schmitt in his analysis of modernity, etc., but that almost goes without saying.
Nicely said, but regarding Schmitt, I think that Strauss thought Schmitt was entirely too modern and dependent on Hobbes. As I argued in part 2 of this series, in Strauss’s hands, Schmitt’s analysis of the political can be detached from modernity and deduced rather neatly from Nietzsche’s philosophy, which regards spiritual health and moral sublimity as dependent on the closed horizon of a culture as opposed to the open horizons of cosmopolitan civilization.
Interesting analysis, I look forward to reading Part 4.
Strauss’ reasoning sounds rather opportunistic.
What effect has the shift toward classical philosophy instead of historicism had, if any, on the American Right?
‘The epoch which began in “1517 or so” is the modern age: 1517 is the year Luther published his 95 Theses, and the “or so” might reach back to 1513 when Machiavelli first started circulating the manuscript of The Prince, a work of epochal importance according to Strauss.’
Do you agree, on The Prince that is?
If I may comment on one part of your query: As has been discussed in earlier articles, for Strauss the big shift between “ancients and moderns” concerns, on the one hand, politics/government as a means to nurture human nature (which implies, among other things, a teleology of man’s natural purpose), and, alternately, a politics/government based on liberal notions of individual freedom-the idea of positive freedom now being considered the natural state of man, an end in itself.
Paul Gottfried, in his book on Strauss, wants to criticize the very idea of the meaningfulness of such a dyad, and it is true that in many respects the distinction is hardly complete, but I nevertheless believe it to be a reasonable and helpful distinction to make. If I am not mistaken, economist Murray Rothbard also questioned Strauss’ use of this schema. At the same time, we must realize that subtlety was not always in play during the time Strauss wrote, and the catchphrase “man has no nature, only history” was (and still is to a large part) the dominant intellectual meme.
Were his conclusions opportunism? Or was it simply Strauss being Strauss, given what he was? One problem I find with his critical analysis of modernity was his wanting to blame (mostly) German thinkers for today’s social problems. I am happy to be corrected on this point, but the epistemological basis for a moral relativism can easily be found within the work of David Hume, and before that (at least in a “proto” form) within a certain non-Germanic late medieval scholastic nominalism. To lay an inordinate “blame” on German thinking was, in my opinion, an odd stop for him to make. Why he did so, and did not further connect the dots is something I cannot explain, but must leave for others to speculate over. Here, I would recommend the Gottfried book as a starting point, and for some useful hints.
1. The Straussians have had a widespread and overwhelmingly negative effect on the American Right, since Straussians are one strand of the neoconservative movement which has worked to purge the American Right of all incipient racialist and nationalist elements in favor of a purely propositional concept of American identity, which of course guarantees Jewish access to the highest levels of power. See my review of Paul Gottfried’s book Leo Strauss and the Conservative Movement in America: https://counter-currents.com/2014/01/paul-gottfrieds-leo-strauss-the-conservative-movement-in-america/
2. Strauss’s turn toward the Ancients is somewhat superficial, since Straussians read the Ancients through modern metaphysical and political lenses, yielding a Plato, an Aristotle, etc. tailored to the tastes of 20th-century Jewish atheists. But Strauss, of course, cannot entirely control how other people read the Ancients, and his rediscovery of esoteric writing can be detached from his own prejudices and agenda and be employed profitably to make the books of the ancients speak again. And that is good, because classical political philosophy supports New Right ideas far more than it supports modern liberal democracy.
3. I do think that Machiavelli is a crucial thinker in defining the modern political project.
I mean, say what you want about the tenets of National Socialism, Dude, at least it’s an ethos.
My bad, I should have put in the whole Big Lebowski quote, referencing nihilism. Even Walter Sobchak (a character partly based on Jewish film director John Milius) knows that National Socialism isn’t nihilism! On this point, Sobchak is a better philosopher than Strauss.
There’s a lot of people on the right, American conservatives usually of the Christian religious persuasion, who go around calling anything they don’t like “nihilism.” I doubt most of them have ever heard of Strauss, but Strauss has certainly influenced them, indirectly.
If you have Paywall access,
simply login first to see your comment auto-approved.
Note on comments privacy & moderation
Your email is never published nor shared.
Comments are moderated. If you don't see your comment, please be patient. If approved, it will appear here soon. Do not post your comment a second time.