1,130 words
In The Machiavellians: Defenders of Freedom,[1] James Burnham sets forth a Machiavellian method for interpreting political texts. (Methods of interpretation are also known as “hermeneutic” methods.) Burnham distinguishes between the “formal” and the “real” meanings of texts. The formal meaning of a text is “what it explicitly states when taken at face value” (p. 8). The formal meaning also expresses, albeit in an indirect and disguised manner, “what may be called the real meaning” (p. 8). The real meaning is what a text signifies “in terms of the actual world of space, time, and events” (p. 9).
The distinction between formal and real meaning cannot be reduced to conscious deception or even self-deception, although these often occur. Rather, Burnham seems simply to assume that there is always a gap between what we say about the world and the world itself, although he also thinks that science can considerably narrow that gap.
To demonstrate the Machiavellian method, Burnham interprets Dante’s De Monarchia (circa 1312–1313). In De Monarchia, Dante argues that mankind should be governed by a single monarchical state, an “empire.” Second, he argues that the Holy Roman Emperor is the legitimate ruler of all mankind. Third, he argues that the authority of the Emperor is independent of that of the Pope.
Dante’s starting point is that the natural end of mankind is the full development of our faculties, which can only take place in the afterlife in the eternal beatific vision of God granted to the saved. The aim of politics is to support this goal, which requires peace. Peace can best be secured by eliminating all competing sovereignties and establishing a global government. There is one God, and one natural end of man, so why shouldn’t there be one political order?
The Roman Empire is the legitimate ruler of the world because Christ was incarnated under Augustus. The Holy Roman Empire is merely the continuation of the Roman Empire.
The independence of the Emperor from the Pope follows from the fact that “Christ, Paul, and even the angel who appeared to Paul acknowledged the temporal authority of the emperor” (p. 7). The idea of two supreme authorities, one temporal and one spiritual, also harmonizes with the dual nature of man.
Burnham regards the formal meaning of De Monarchia with utmost disdain. Dante’s idea of man’s ultimate end is “meaningless” (p. 8). The idea of a world empire is “utopian and materially impossible” (p. 8). Dante’s arguments are more bad than good, but even the good ones are “completely irrelevant” to real-world politics. Thus, taken at face value De Monarchia is “worthless, totally worthless” (p. 8). (Perhaps we should count our blessings that Burnham did not go on to interpret The Divine Comedy.)
But then, with a conjurer’s flourish, Burnham produces his Machiavellian decoder ring and reveals the actual meaning of De Monarchia. It turns out that Dante was a partisan of the Ghibelline defenders of the Holy Roman Empire against the Guelph defenders of papal supremacy. After a brief summary of the Ghibelline-Guelph contest up to Dante’s time and place (fourteenth-century Florence), Burnham concludes that the “real meaning” of De Monarchia is “simply an impassioned propagandistic defense of the point of view of the turncoat Bianchi [Ghibelline] exiles from Florence, specifically; and more generally of the broader Ghibelline point of view . . . De Monarchia is, we might say, a Ghibelline Party Platform” (pp. 17–18). According to Burhnam, Dante’s “practical political aims toward his country were traitorous; his sociological allegiance was reactionary, backward-looking” (pp. 18–19). Indeed, Dante was an enemy of “progress.”
Burnham then sums up the Machiavellian method of interpretation.
First, there is almost always a sharp distinction between the formal and real meaning of political texts.
Second, formal meanings are usually supernatural or metaphysical, and hence meaningless — or they are simply utopian: meaningful, perhaps, but unrealizable.
Third, formal meanings, regardless of their logical validity, are “necessarily irrelevant to real political problems” (p. 22).
Fourth, the formal meaning both disguises and indirectly expresses the real meaning; i.e., “the concrete meaning of the political treatise taken in its real context, in its relation to the actualities of the social and historical situation in which it functions” (p. 22).
Fifth, because the formal meaning is not the real meaning, debating the formal meaning entails leaving the real meaning “irresponsible” (p. 22). The Machiavellian hermeneutical method’s purpose is to disclose the real agendas behind political texts and compel them to defend themselves.
Burnham makes a great show of dismissing religious, metaphysical, and utopian speculation from political theory. But he implicitly dispenses with moral philosophy as well. By taking political theories as mere propaganda for established political agendas, he treats these agendas simply as “given preferences,” much as economists treat consumer preferences as given.

You can buy Greg Johnson’s From Plato to Postmodernism here
But the fact that people happen to want something does not mean that they ought to want it. Moral philosophy seeks both to discard and to generate preferences based on an understanding of the ends that we ought to prefer.
Burnham assumes that Dante’s given political preferences generate his political philosophy. But couldn’t Dante’s more fundamental philosophical convictions have generated his political preferences? Anyone who has changed his political preferences after encountering better arguments knows that such changes are possible. Yet, this possibility is ruled out in advance by Burnham’s method. Thus, it is a bad method.
Before Burnham was a Machiavellian, he was a Marxist. Marxism holds that philosophy both expresses and distorts underlying material interests. When Burnham moved from Marx to Machiavelli, it is tempting to say that the (Machiavellian) apple did not fall far from the (Marxist) tree. But the metaphor needs to be reversed, because Machiavelli is the tree of which all modern political philosophies are the fruits, Marxism included.
Burnham assumes that social and political conditions give rise to philosophical outlooks. But this conviction is itself a philosophical outlook — which, if Burnham is correct, is itself the expression of a prior political program.
What was Machiavelli’s political agenda? Burnham thinks that Machiavelli’s aims were limited to the unification of Italy, which is a noble and worthwhile aim.
But Machiavelli’s agenda was far more sweeping. He aimed to overthrow classical political philosophy, which is founded on norms, and replace it with modern political philosophy, which is founded on given preferences.
Why? Because Machiavelli believed that a political order based on something low but common to all men—namely the satisfaction of their given preferences—would be more stable than a political order founded upon high but rarely achieved ideals.
But what is this political order? Ultimately, it is what we call modernity: the organization of society around the satisfaction of human desire through the mastery of nature by science and technology.
Has Machiavelli defeated classical political philosophy? No, because we can always ask: “Is modernity the right thing to choose?”
* * *
Counter-Currents has extended special privileges to those who donate $120 or more per year.
- First, donor comments will appear immediately instead of waiting in a moderation queue. (People who abuse this privilege will lose it.)
- Second, donors will have immediate access to all Counter-Currents posts. Non-donors will find that one post a day, five posts a week will be behind a “Paywall” and will be available to the general public after 30 days.
- Third, Paywall members have the ability to edit their comments.
- Fourth, Paywall members can “commission” a yearly article from Counter-Currents. Just send a question that you’d like to have discussed to [email protected]. (Obviously, the topics must be suitable to Counter-Currents and its broader project, as well as the interests and expertise of our writers.)
To get full access to all content behind the paywall, sign up here:
Paywall Gift Subscriptions
If you are already behind the paywall and want to share the benefits, Counter-Currents also offers paywall gift subscriptions. We need just five things from you:
- your payment
- the recipient’s name
- the recipient’s email address
- your name
- your email address
To register, just fill out this form and we will walk you through the payment and registration process. There are a number of different payment options.
Note
[1] James Burham, The Machiavellians: Defenders of Freedom (1943) (London: Lume Books, 2020).
Enjoyed this article?
Be the first to leave a tip in the jar!
11 comments
I missed the first part of the stream but I would like to know how you arrived at your contention that Signor Machiavelli aimed to overthrow a classical political philosophy of norms with one based on given preferences.
To my mind The Prince ‘s main theme seems to be the utility and, in a complex international political environment, the necessity of not slavishly following the dictates of Catholic teachings, this being especially required of the small, weak Italian states, his beloved Florence in particular. He only proposes this in the realm of statecraft though and really he was just saying out loud what much of the ruling class already took for granted. Christendom wouldn’t have survived for twelve centuries if at least some potentates hadn’t understood this.
It seems most unfair to ascribe to him the situation that now pertains. His main concern was that Florence, by building a citizen army, should be strong and prosper and beyond that he wished that Italy should be politically united in order to exclude the Hapsburg and French Empires.
Whenever Machiavelli rebukes utopianism, virtue, and high standards of behavior, he is referring to classical political philosophy.
I think Burnham would respond that asking whether ‘modernity’ is the ‘right’ thing to do smacks of utopianism. Modernity has happened. Any thought of changing it is playing right into the hands of modernity.
The moral dichotomy isn’t between good choices and bad choices.
It’s between a belief in choice or a belief in fate.
Once you’ve accepted ‘choice’ as an option, you’re ‘doing modernity’.
Modernity was not a “fate.” It was a utopian project launched by people like Machiavelli under the cloak of “realism.” Bad projects can be questioned, halted, and replaced with better ones. We have the freedom to do that.
Remember to read your Machiavelli, and do not take anyone else’s opinion for what he said, what he meant, or what you would think of his work if you spent a good amount of time on it, trying to reduce the role of your preconceptions to a minimum.
Machiavelli states that classical political philosophers such as Plato and Aristotle wrote about what ought to be, whereas he himself wrote about how the real world actually worked, how real rulers actually behaved and which policies were effective. Machiavelli saw himself as merely a messenger, a cataloguer, a scientist.
That’s how he presented himself, but in fact he was advancing an alternative set of norms by which he wished to reshape facts.
So you’re saying his formal meaning was different from his intended purpose. 😉
You should interview Ed Dutton about this. Although incredibly reductive, he synthesizes contemporary politics with Machiavelli in the most articulate way I’ve ever heard. He claims leftists are the most Machiavellian and individualistic because they use woke/postmodernism/cultural Marxism (whatever you want to call it) as a ‘crucible of evolution’ against rightist whites, thereby carving out an ‘individualist’ space for themselves to dominate their allied diversity. I don’t think this strategy is anything new because it was the basis of Helter Skelter.
Ha good name. I was going to say the January 6th proceedings are a good example of machiavelli’s effective use of cruelty. Yes, the left is the most Machiavellian, in the common sense of the term, not burnham’s.
Idly I wonder how much of Burnham’s awareness of doublethink rhetoric is due to his years in the Bolshy and Trotskyist swamps. He didn’t really know his Partisan Review colleague, Orwell, but he had a profound influence on him in his last years, particularly upon Nineteen Eighty-Four, where Burnham explained the whole rationale of Ingsoc and Stalinism.
Comments are closed.
If you have a Subscriber access,
simply login first to see your comment auto-approved.
Note on comments privacy & moderation
Your email is never published nor shared.
Comments are moderated. If you don't see your comment, please be patient. If approved, it will appear here soon. Do not post your comment a second time.
Paywall Access
Lost your password?Edit your comment