2,151 words
Author’s Note:
The following text is based on a transcript by Rollo Walker of a 1999 lecture on “Objectivity, Relativism, and Well-Being.” This text only includes the first half of the transcript, and it has been massively condensed and rewritten.
Socrates is famous for arguing that all human beings pursue happiness; specifically, he said that we are all searching for the good, and when we finally figure out what the good is, it’s happiness, or well-being. The Greek word is “eudaimonia.”
The Socratic position is based on the observation that in any given situation we always have a certain range of options. Sometimes we have many options. Sometimes we have only a few. We also have the freedom to choose among them. Given that we always have some options, and given the freedom to choose among those options, human beings will always choose the option that seems to them the best. Even if we decide to kill ourselves, presumably this is because we think that death is the better option. So by the very nature of human rationality, human choice, and human action, there’s a directedness towards what is regarded as good. Human beings are pursuing the good in every choice, and Socrates argues that ultimately the good life for man is happiness.
If we’re all pursuing happiness, then the only choice we have in the matter is how to pursue happiness, whether to pursue it intelligently or not. This essay is really for people who wish to pursue it intelligently. No further thought or reading is required to pursue it stupidly.
The claim that human beings are all pursuing happiness runs up against what we can call the Jeffrey Dahmer problem. If Jeffrey Dahmer, serial killer and cannibal, was pursuing happiness, we have to conclude that some people pursue happiness in really strange ways. To handle such examples, we have to put a lot of weight on the provisos that from the choices available to us, we choose the best as we see it. All human beings choose the good as they see it from the options that are available to them. So if we object to Jeffrey Dahmer’s decisions, Socrates would say that’s because we think he was mistaken about the good. Jeffrey Dahmer could have spent his evenings visiting sick people or going to the library, or reading to improve his mind, but instead he lured people back to his apartment, killed them, had sex with them, and ate them. Why? Because of all the options available as he saw it, that was the best use of his time. Now, again, he was gravely mistaken about that, according to Socrates, but still, the structure of his action was oriented toward the good as he saw it.
The corollary of the claim that we’re always pursuing the good as we see it is this: Nobody chooses evil as such. Meaning: nobody does something that they regard as evil. Nobody chooses to do evil as evil. They only choose evil because they think it is good. People only choose evil under the guise of the good. Even people who loudly proclaim they are doing evil, are only doing “evil”—evil in scare quotes, meaning evil as other people see it, not evil as they see it. The rebellious teenagers who get into Satanism and heavy metal are embracing what their parents see as “evil”—but they do this because they think that upsetting their parents is a good thing to do.
Now we need to introduce the concepts of virtue and vice. To do that, we need to distinguish between a potentiality and a propensity. A potentiality is simply the ability to do something. A propensity is an inclination to do something. Virtues are propensities to do the good. Vices are propensities to do evil. A person has the potential to do both good and evil, but a virtuous person tends toward the good and a vicious person tends toward the evil.
For Socrates, virtue is simply knowledge of the good. Vice is simply ignorance of the good. Virtue is the propensity to do the right thing at the right place and the right time. The virtue of courage is a kind of knowledge of when to fight and when not to fight, when to hold oneself back or run away. The vice of cowardice is a lack of knowledge of when it’s appropriate to stand one’s ground. To the coward, a bad act appears as the best option, namely running away when he shouldn’t. Vice is a kind of derangement of the mind, a clouding of our moral sensibilities, so the things that aren’t good show up as good, and things that are good show up as bad.
But how is simple knowledge or ignorance of the good a propensity to act? Can’t we know the right thing but not do it? Don’t we need an additional motivational factor to turn knowledge or ignorance of the good into a propensity to act in good or bad ways? For Socrates, the answer is simple. The good is what motivates us to act. Once one thinks something is good, that alone is sufficient motive to do it. One does not need an additional reason or incentive to do it.
Of course things are more complicated than that. For instance, parents who wish to raise virtuous children, and legislators who wish to mold virtuous citizens, use rewards and punishments as additional incentives to virtuous behavior. And Aristotle in his Nicomachean Ethics analyzes the phenomenon of “weakness of will” (akrasia), in which people who know what is good fail to do it. But Aristotle’s analysis preserves Socrates’ essential claim that to know the good is to do it. But one does need to add some caveats. First, one must be a mature moral agent, not a child or a childish adult. Second, our knowledge of the good cannot be overwhelmed by passion. Third, sometimes people can know what is right but fail to see the applicability of this knowledge in particular circumstances. But when one sees clearly, unimpeded by passion, knowledge of the good alone is enough to lead to virtuous action.
Does Socrates believe that evil people are morally culpable? After all, he holds that nobody chooses evil as evil. We all have good intentions. We all mean well. If we all mean well, are people who choose to do bad things culpable? The simple answer is yes, we are morally culpable because we have a moral obligation to know the truth about what’s right and wrong. In fact, we are highly motivated to know the difference, because the good life is what we are all pursuing. So ignorance of the truth about the most important things in life is highly blameworthy.
The deep metaphysical assumption of Socrates’ ethics is that there’s a right and wrong answer about what the good is. If you can be right or wrong about the good life, that means that there’s some kind of objective standard of what constitutes goodness. For Socrates, this standard is provided by nature. For Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, there is what is right “by nature” as opposed to what is right “by convention.” But our opinions and conventions about what is right can be mistaken by the standard of what is right by nature.
How are norms given by nature? The clearest example is physical health. Doctors, nutritionists, and physical trainers know from observation what makes the human body healthy and what makes it sick. Socrates and Plato define virtue as the health of the soul and vice as a sickness of the soul.
The question then becomes: “How do you discover what the sickness and the health of the soul are?” The answer is: essentially the same way that doctors determine what makes the body healthy or sick. Medicine is both empirical and normative. Ninety-eight point six is held up as the normal temperature. How have we discovered this? By looking at how humans flourish and how they suffer. Ethics can be a science in the exact same way by observing the nature of the soul and what makes it flourish and what makes it sick. And just as knowledge makes doctors authorities about health and sickness, knowledge can make moral philosophers authorities about virtue and vice.
The greatest challenge to Socratic moral realism is moral relativism. Moral relativism is the most wide-spread belief about ethics in our culture today. Relativism is the claim that there are no objective moral truths. Instead, what counts as moral truth is relative. To say a truth is relative is to say that it is not true for everyone. It is true for only a subset of people: for a particular culture or for a sovereign individual who creates his own values.
Relativism is basically the idea that in the pursuit of happiness, there are no right or wrong answers. Each individual has the sovereign authority to set norms for himself, and you can’t be wrong about these norms. So, if you want to declare that something is good for you, you have the sovereign power to declare that that is good for you. Relativism is an ancient idea. It is as old as youth itself. It merely makes a philosophy of the youthful attitude that whatever is me is good.
If moral relativism is true, you can stop reading here, because relativism implies that the intelligent pursuit of happiness is no better than the stupid or mindless pursuit of happiness, because all answers have an equal claim to truth. If moral relativism is true, there are no wrong answers. So, you don’t have to think or work very hard to live a good life. You can be passive, and you can be secure in your passivity that no one can challenge the choices that you’ve made.
If relativism is the view that human beings can decide at will that one thing is good (for them) and another thing is evil (for them), and they can’t be wrong, then if relativism were true, what outcome would we predict in the pursuit of happiness? Obviously, virtually everybody would be happy. Why? Because relativism basically claims that in the game of life, each person gets to make up the rules as he goes along. And under those circumstances, you’d have to be a complete moron or lunatic not to win.
If you and I are playing a game of cards and you have the power to change the rules at any point, you would almost necessarily win, unless you just didn’t care about it. Because no matter what cards I put down, you could say, “Well, in the previous round, that would have been a winning hand, but this is the fourth round, and so all the rules are reversed.” And I’d say, “Okay, take my money.” And we’d keep playing, and you’d keep changing the rules, and you’d come out the winner.
The strong relativist claim is that individuals get to decide what makes them happy, and they can’t be wrong. If the relativist is right, the question is: Why in the world would anyone be unhappy? What’s your excuse for losing the game of life if you can rig it in your favor? There would be no excuse! It would be an extraordinarily odd thing to find anybody who’s unhappy if they can define happiness for them, and no one can say that they’re wrong.
But the fact is that most people are unhappy. I’m a fairly happy guy, but I am not entirely happy with my life. But if relativism were true, then I can define whatever I’m doing, in the very minute I am doing it, as happiness. And in that case, I should be completely happy in every moment. But I don’t have that superpower, which means that moral relativism is false.
My refutation of moral relativism is a simple modus tollens syllogism:
i. If moral relativism were true, then anyone who wants to be happy would be entirely happy.
ii. Most people are not happy.
____________________________
Therefore, moral relativism is false.
Life is a game. There are rules, there are risks, and there are winners and losers. If moral relativism is true, then life is not a very serious game. If you can define your own happiness and can’t be wrong about it, then you can’t really lose. You’ve got no excuse for not being happy already.
But you’re not happy. Which means that relativism is false. There are right and wrong ways of living our lives. And if we are unhappy, we are doing something wrong. We are missing some important truths about the pursuit of happiness. This means that we need to start taking life seriously, which means taking moral questions seriously, which means taking philosophy seriously. Because the stakes we are playing for are our very lives.
Objectivity%2C%20Relativism%2C%20and%23038%3B%20the%20Pursuit%20of%20Happiness
Share
Enjoyed this article?
Be the first to leave a tip in the jar!
Related
-
Eric Kaufmann on White Extinction & White Genocide
-
Christmas Special: Merry Christmas, Infidels!
-
Jean Raspail’s The Camp of the Saints
-
It’s Time to STOP Shopping for Christmas
-
Counter-Currents Radio Podcast No. 614
-
Decameron Film Festival 2024
-
Cohousing:
An Ancient Idea Whose Time has Come -
Remembering René Guénon: November 15, 1886–January 7, 1951
10 comments
The weak point in this argument is the assumption that people want happiness, which is false.
If people were to want happiness they would simply get on drugs, nothing can beat that as far as pure happiness is concerned.
But people don’t want happiness, they want things which are out there in reality and these things, no matter if objectively or arbitrarily/individually defined as being of “value”, are not under our control, there is no guarantee that we will (always) get them. The result is that we are doomed (or we doom ourselves) to hope and fear, to go up and down in ecstasy and agony as the fortune wants it, over achieving/reaching those value-things over which we have ultimately no control.
“If people were to want happiness they would simply get on drugs, nothing can beat that as far as pure happiness is concerned.” You are confusing hedonism(sensual pleasure) with happiness(eudaimonia). Drug addicts are not happy. Too mush hedonism interferes with happiness.
You are confusing hedonism(sensual pleasure) with happiness(eudaimonia).
Then you will have to define what you mean by “happiness” because you are using the word with a different meaning than the usual one. With poorly defined terms you can’prove’ anything.
A good piece by Greg Johnson. Returning to Socrates, Plato and Aristotle always produces in me the effect of listening to JS Bach’s 48 after having had my ears assaulted by heavy metal or hip hop.
Absolute epistomological relativism is of course self-contradictory. But I am not convinced that moral relativism is refuted by Greg’s syllogism: which is, as they say, valid, but not sound. I would say that his first premise is not universally true, for there are causes of unhappiness that lie without the moral sphere, such as pain.
But in any case, outside of the criminally insane, there are few true moral relativists. In the political sphere maybe there are none, not even on the furthest fringes. For all politics, even anarchism, constrains the actions of the individual to the mores of the collective.
Relativism in politics, culture and art is merely a stratagem of the Left to disrupt and discredit the traditional order. For who indeed are more puritanical and absolutist than the current high media intelligentsia and academic establishment when one of their (daily more numerous) shibboleths and taboos is breached?
“because relativism implies that the intelligent pursuit of happiness is no better than the stupid or mindless pursuit of happiness”
Relativism does not make value statements of this kind. “Better” in this case, is a value statement of a particular nature constituted to prefer particular outcomes and express itself in a particular way. Happiness itself is not a definite goal, and “stupid” and “intelligent” in this sense appear strictly related to the existential dimension, which is itself a problem, since the existence of a pauper is what it is precisely due to the nature of a pauper, as much as king’s is that of a king for the same reason.
Indeed, the mindless pursuit of happiness is not better – *for the person who is fashioned to pursue “happiness” “intelligently”. (pursuit of happiness is an idiosyncratic combination of words which describes a certain mechanic and conveys the speakers intimate relation to that mechanic vis-a-vis his own dispositions and that of his culture)
“because all answers have an equal claim to truth. If moral relativism is true, there are no wrong answers.”
Nietzsche has made an unsurpassed analysis of how the word “truth” deployed in this fashion in his essay “On Truth and Lies in an Extra-Moral Sense”, To try to add anything more to that would be wasteful. (the last statement is not an absolute truth, it conveys a disposition of the author).
To me, it seems that the stronger counter to Socrates is rejecting eudaimonia outright as the basis for good living. To stay with the Greek, I think that “telos” is the stronger basis for morality, a more objective foundation for the “good life,” and provides a much stronger counter to the Jeffrey Dahmer problem. But more importantly, I have a hard time seeing how rejecting moral relativism from a eudaimonia-based ethic puts one in a position to reject universalism, and/or to grant biological differences in groups (“to say a truth is relative is to say that it is not true for everyone…”).
It’s a good starting point, but I think that the nationalist ought to reject happiness as the basis for morality. It can be an excellent gauge (the happy person is PROBABLY living a wise and ethical life), but it is not the measure of the good life.
On the pursuit of Happiness in the Ethno-State:
Assuming an all-white society/ geographical region, there will always be a need for performance of the lowest skill, menial and/ or disgusting work.
Do we really want even the bottom 10% of a white population lowering themselves to perform this work?
Of course not. Therefore we will alwsys need to import, even temporarily, other races to do this.
Right?
Wrong.
Also, in a White Ethno-State, where will we get the “dancing monkeys”? E.g. football, basketball players, musical entertainers etc?
Only via TV? No more live in person real-time gladiators?
“human beings will always choose the option that seems to them the best”
“Human beings are pursuing the good in every choice”
I didnt read the whole article and im not sure if you agree with Socrates, but I sort of disagree with this premise. Humans will do whatever their DNA tells them to do. The set of instructions that determined how their body would build itself also determines how they think and behave. Often we are unable to make good decisions because of our nature.
If our decisions are not good enough, we die without reproducing. Therefore our decisions are based on the natures of our ancestors, as well as our own little genetic mutation inspired identity. In this sense, as genetic mutations are random, our choices are arbitrary, predicted only by the laws of natural and sexual selection. So I don’t think this concept of “good” comes into the equation. It is in a sense a very nihilistic and anti-free-will philosophy but it seems accurate to me.
Comments are closed.
If you have a Subscriber access,
simply login first to see your comment auto-approved.
Note on comments privacy & moderation
Your email is never published nor shared.
Comments are moderated. If you don't see your comment, please be patient. If approved, it will appear here soon. Do not post your comment a second time.
Paywall Access
Lost your password?Edit your comment